Art and social life. G

The first Russian Marxist, outstanding literary critic and art theorist Georgy Valentinovich Plekhanov was born on December 11, 1856 in the village of Gudalovka, Lipetsk district, Tambov province (now the village of Plekhanovo, Gryazinsky district). His father, a poor Tambov landowner, Valentin Petrovich Plekhanov, was a stern man and demanding of himself and those around him. From his mother Maria Feodorovna, née Belinskaya (the grandniece of V.G. Belinsky), Georgy inherited kindness, impressionability, and attention to people.

The Plekhanovs' house had a large library, which was dominated by books on military affairs. Georgy sat in it for hours and, having read books on the art of war, decided to devote himself to military service. He successfully passed the entrance exams to the Voronezh Military Gymnasium and was immediately enrolled in the second grade.

In addition to studying military sciences, Georgy Plekhanov worked a lot on himself, became acquainted with the works of the classics of Russian literature, the best works of critics of the revolutionary-democratic camp. The names of Pushkin, Lermontov, Nekrasov, Belinsky, Chernyshevsky became close to him throughout his life.

In 1873, Plekhanov graduated from a military gymnasium (his father had died shortly before) and entered the Konstantinovsky Military School, where he did not stay long, only a few months, after which he resigned and returned to his homeland - the village of Gudalovka. From here at the end of March 1874 he went to St. Petersburg, where he successfully passed the entrance exams to the Mining Institute.

While studying at the school and then at the Mining Institute, G.V. Plekhanov visited his native places several times, lived in Gudalovka and Lipetsk. The amazing nature of the Black Earth Region, the first impressions of childhood and adolescence, undoubtedly influenced the formation of his aesthetic tastes.

“When I met the “green town” - Lipetsk, truly immersed in greenery, with its wonderful location on the hills, from which an unforgettable view of the Voronezh River valley opens, with its shining ponds, lakes, lush meadows and dense coniferous forests - I said to myself: I now understand Georgy Valentinovich’s love for everything beautiful, for nature, animals, sculpture, poetry. Here, in Lipetsk, this poetic side of Georgy Valentinovich’s nature developed,” 1 - this is what his wife Rosalia Markovna wrote after visiting Plekhanov’s homeland in 1927.

In 1876, G.V. Plekhanov finally took the revolutionary path, and in the summer of 1877 he was expelled from the institute. Plekhanov's worldview underwent a complex evolution. Initially the leader of the populist organization “Land and Freedom,” he, under the influence of the ideas of Marxism, breaks with populism and becomes a passionate supporter and propagandist of Marxist ideas in Russia.

From January 1880 until the February Revolution of 1917, Plekhanov lived in exile (Switzerland, Italy, France).

Actively participating in the struggle of ideas, Plekhanov wrote many works on aesthetics. His interest in issues of art was constant.

The period from 1883 to 1903 was the most fruitful in the work of Plekhanov, a literary critic. During these years the following works were written: “Belinsky and reasonable reality” (1897), “Belinsky’s literary views” (1897), “Chernyshevsky’s aesthetic theory” (1897), “Letters without an address” (1899-1900).

In them, Plekhanov defended revolutionary democratic traditions in aesthetics and criticism. Among Marx's followers, he did more than anyone else to apply historical materialism to aesthetics, the theory of art and literature.

Plekhanov's notable theoretical and critical speeches include the articles “The Proletarian Movement and Bourgeois Art” (1905), “Henrik Ibsen” (1906), “On the Psychology of the Labor Movement” (1907), “Art and Social Life” (1912-1913) , articles about L.N. Tolstoy, as well as numerous letters from Plekhanov to figures of literature and art.

Returning to Russia on March 31 (April 13), 1917, Plekhanov witnessed the October Revolution, but did not accept it, although he did not oppose Soviet power.

According to his own dying wish, he was buried at the Volkov cemetery in Leningrad, near the graves of Belinsky and Dobrolyubov, dear to him. Plekhanov's archive and library are kept in the Plekhanov House, specially created in Leningrad.

Lipetsk residents honor the memory of their fellow countryman. In 1928 Gudalovka was renamed into the village. Plekhanov, in the same year Prodolnaya Street in Lipetsk was renamed Plekhanov Street. In 1972, Plekhanov Square at the intersection of Plekhanov and Zegel streets was named in his honor. A memorial museum for G.V. Plekhanov was opened in Lipetsk, on which a memorial plaque was installed in 1956. On October 30, 1998, a sculpture by G. V. Plekhanov (author E. A. Volfson) was installed in front of the house-museum. December 6, 2006 in the village. Plekhanov, Gryazinsky district, a memorial sign was unveiled in honor of the 150th anniversary of the birth of G.V. Plekhanov (sculptor I. Mazur).

1 Berezhansky A. Years at home // Interlocutor. – Voronezh, 1971. – P. 90.

Author's works

  • Works: in 24 volumes - M.-Pg., 1923-1928. – (Institute of the European Union of Marx and F. Engels. Library of scientific socialism).
  • Literary heritage: in 8 volumes - M.: Mosekgiz, 1934-1940.
  • Selected philosophical works: in 5 volumes - M.: Gospolitizdat, 1956-1958.
  • Selected works / comp., author. entry Art. and comment. S. V. Tyutyukin. – M.: Rosspen, 2010. – 550 p. – (B-ka of Russian social thought from ancient times to the beginning of the 20th century).
  • For twenty years: Sat. articles lit., economics. and philosophical-historical – Petersburg, 1905. – 652 p.
  • On the tasks of socialists in the fight against hunger in Russia. – St. Petersburg. : Ed. M. Malykh, 1906. – 84 p.
  • Articles about Tolstoy / preface. V. Vaganyan. – Moscow: Gosizdat, [b. G.]. – 95 ​​s.
  • N. G. Chernyshevsky. – Petersburg: Rosehip, 1910. – 537 p.
  • December 14, 1825: speech delivered at the Russian meeting in Geneva, December 14-27, 1900. – Pg: Gosizdat, 1921. – 31 p.
  • Art: Sat. Art. / entry Art. L. Axelrod-Orthodox and W. Fritsche. – M.: New Moscow, 1922. – 216 p.
  • Art and social life. – M.: Moscow Institute of Journalism, 1922. – 68 p.
  • Predecessors of K. Marx and F. Engels. – M.: Moscow worker, 1922. – 230 p.
  • V. G. Belinsky: collection. art. – M.-Pg., 1923. – 333 p.
  • A. I. Herzen: collection. Art. – M., 1924. – 215 p.
  • Art and literature. – M.: Goslitizdat, 1948. – 888 p.
  • Letters without an address. Art and social life / afterword. and note. U. Guralnik. – M.: Goslitizdat, 1956. – 248 p.
  • Literature and aesthetics: in 2 volumes / prepared. text, intro. Art. and comment. B.I. Bursova. – M.: Goslitizdat, 1958. – (Monuments of world aesthetic and critical thought).
  • Philosophical and literary heritage of G. V. Plekhanov: in 3 volumes - M.: Nauka, 1973.
  • Aesthetics and sociology of art: in 2 volumes / intro. Art. M. A. Lifshitz; note I. L. Galinskaya. – M.: Art, 1978. – (History of aesthetics in monuments and documents).
  • Political testament: pro et contra (Last thoughts of G. V. Plekhanov) / ed. A. Berezhansky. – Lipetsk: De facto, 2006. – 120 p.

Literature about life and creativity

  • Aptekman O.V. Georgy Valentinovich Plekhanov: from personal memories / O.V. Aptekman. – L.: Kolos, 1924. – 96 p.
  • Klokov A. Yu. On the history of the G. V. Plekhanov Museum in Lipetsk // Bartenev readings: materials from the interregion. conf. November 18-19, 2003 – Lipetsk, 2005. – P. 113-117.
  • Berezhansky A. Plekhanov lived here: a museum of the man who predicted the consequences of the revolution: [history of the creation of the Plekhanov Museum in Lipetsk. Exposition] // Museum. – 2005. – No. 5. – P. 34-35.
  • Berezhansky A. S. Plekhanov: from populism to Marxism / A. S. Berezhansky. – 2nd ed., revised. and additional – M.: Rosspen, 2006. – 264 p. – (Plekhanov Foundation Library).
  • Georgy Valentinovich Plekhanov and figures of Russian culture: photo album. – Lipetsk: De facto, 2006. – 33 p. – (To the 150th anniversary of G.V. Plekhanov).
  • Georgy Valentinovich Plekhanov: on the 150th anniversary of the philosopher, thinker and public figure. – Lipetsk: Lipets. region Museum of Local Lore: Respect, 2006. – 130 p.
  • The soul is full of memories: Georgy Valentinovich Plekhanov and the Lipetsk region: from the collections of the Lipetsk Regional Scientific Library, the State Archive of the Lipetsk Region and the archive department of the city of Lipetsk. – Lipetsk, 2006. – 143 p.: ill.; 1 CD (CD-R).
  • Historical and philosophical heritage of G. V. Plekhanov and modernity: materials of the All-Russian Federation. scientific-practical conf., dedicated 150th anniversary of the birth of G. V. Plekhanov, December 5-6. 2006 – Lipetsk: Institute for Educational Development, 2006. – 199 p.
  • Catalog of the memorial fund of G. V. Plekhanov. – Lipetsk: Lipets. region Museum of Local Lore, 2006. – 31 p.
  • Plekhanov Georgy Valentinovich (1856-1918) // Outstanding economists of Russia and the world: collection. scientific works – Lipetsk: Leningrad State Pedagogical University, 2006. – pp. 12-20.: photo.
  • Nenakhov A.V. On the historical views of G.V. Plekhanov // Interuniversity scientific and methodological readings in memory of K.F. Kalaidovich: collection. materials. – Yelets, 2006. – Issue 7. – P. 99-101.: ill., photo.
  • Shchukina E. P. Georgy Valentinovich Plekhanov: [according to archive. materials] // Bulletin of the archivist. – 2006. – Issue. 1. – pp. 130-134.
  • Koltakov V. M. House-museum of G. V. Plekhanov // Historical and memorable places of Lipetsk / V. M. Koltakov, A. V. Ovchinnikov. – Lipetsk: De facto, 2007. – P. 77-83.: photo.
  • Grigoriev E.K. Marx and his “disciples” in the homeland of Leninism: [G. V. Plekhanov, mentioned. documents from GALO] // Questions of history. – 2007. – No. 1. – P. 58-78.
  • Shakhov V. Great son of the Understeppe // Rising. – 2007. – No. 5. – P. 176-183.
  • Gudukhin V. Illumination: a documentary story about the life and work of G. V. Plekhanov / V. Gudukhin. – Lipetsk: Neon City, 2008. – 67 p.

Reference materials

  • Social thought in Russia in the 18th and early 20th centuries. : encyclopedia. – M., 2005. – P. 404-407.: ill.
  • Voronezh Historical and Cultural Encyclopedia. – 2nd ed. – Voronezh, 2009. – P. 413.
  • Lipetsk encyclopedia. – Lipetsk, 2001. – T. 3. – P. 62-66.
  • Tambov encyclopedia. – Tambov, 2004. – P. 446-447. : portrait
  • Bunin Encyclopedia / author-comp. A. V. Dmitriev. – Lipetsk, 2010. – P. 578-579.: portrait.
  • Glorious names of the land of Lipetsk: biogr. reference about the known writers, scientists, educators, artists. – Lipetsk, 2007. – P. 271-277.: ill.
  • History of Russian literature of the late XIX – early XX centuries: bibliogr. decree. / ed. K. D. Muratova. – M.-L., 1963. – P. 339-347.
  • Russian writers. 1800-1917: biogr. dictionary. – M., 1999. – T. 4. – P. 642-647. : portrait
  • Social and political figures of the Lipetsk region: biobibliogr. decree. – Voronezh: Central-Chernozem. book publishing house, 1980. – P. 3-4.
  • Writers of the Lipetsk region: bibliogr. decree. – Voronezh, 1986. – Issue. 1. – pp. 84-88.

Based on the work “Art and Social Life” (1)

... Everything written by Plekhanov on philosophy
...this is the best in all the international literature of Marxism.
V. I. Lenin (2)

Never, perhaps, has Marxism as a philosophical doctrine been subjected to such fierce criticism as in our turbulent times. There are, of course, good reasons for this. This is the collapse of socialist ideals, discredited by Stalinist ideology and economic voluntarism due to the Marxist illiteracy of the leaders, and the unviability of the regimes created by them.

And yet, turning again and again to primary sources, rereading the works of Marx, Engels, Lenin, you come to the conviction that there is no more harmonious and flexible system of views on the world around us, its development and the variety of forms it takes, than the teachings of Marx, based on a materialistic approach to the most diverse manifestations of nature and the human mind.

And if we consider such a branch of human mental activity as aesthetics, then, perhaps, no one has contributed so much to its development and renewal from the perspective of Marxism as the great Russian philosopher G. V. Plekhanov. Perhaps this will sound too loud, especially if we bear in mind the enormous interest that idealistic philosophical systems, created by other great Russian philosophers, such as Solovyov, Fedorov, Bulgakov, Karsavin.

But, as usually happened in Russia, interest was aroused not so much by the fidelity of these systems, but by their long oblivion, closedness from the mass reader, and the bias of official propaganda towards materialism in recent years. Now, it seems, the skew, according to the law of the pendulum, is happening in the other direction.

And therefore, in our opinion, the desire to go against the flow in order to prevent imbalance or, at least, weaken it, becomes especially relevant.

In this sense, Plekhanov’s personality and his works seem to be a natural continuation of that line of Russian thought, which can be designated by such names as Belinsky, Chernyshevsky, Dobrolyubov, Pisarev. Plekhanov brought this line to such a high level that his judgments on aesthetic topics are of considerable interest to a modern researcher. To ward off accusations of Plekhanov’s one-sidedness, it is worth citing the statement of one of the best experts on his work, G. I. Kunitsyn: “G. V. Plekhanov was one of the few followers of K. Marx and F. Engels who (despite numerous literary slander against him in the past) did not reduce either the aesthetic or the artistic only to the class. He was a great master of precisely the clear separation of the universal human essence of the artistic and aesthetic itself from their class application and interpretation.” (3)

Of course, it is difficult in a small work to even briefly touch on all the problems that interested Plekhanov, and therefore we will dwell only on a few issues that he considered in one of the most interesting works, “Art and Social Life.”

The fact is that in it Plekhanov touches on an issue that has not lost its relevance to this day. After all, his civic, aesthetic, and creative position depends on how the artist resolves this issue. Either art for art's sake, or art for society. In order not to misinterpret, it is better to give the floor to the author:

“Some have said and continue to say: man is not made for the Sabbath, but the Sabbath is for man; not society for the artist, but the artist for society. Art should contribute to the development of human consciousness and the improvement of the social order.

Others strongly reject this view. In their opinion, art in itself is a goal; to turn it into a means to achieve some extraneous goals, even the most noble ones, means to humiliate the dignity of a work of art.” (4)

The differences between these two views remain the cause of ongoing controversy to this day and may always exist. Perhaps this contradiction is the driving force behind the development of artistic thought.

However, Plekhanov, as a dialectical Marxist, poses the question differently - not which of these views is more correct, but why one or another view prevails in a given period in the history of a given society. To pose the question this way, one must really have a completely different point of view compared to how others did it.

What conclusion does Plekhanov come to when looking at the relationship between social life and artistic creativity from this angle?

It is worth noting here that the work “Art and Social Life” is notable for the fact that the author draws conclusions from his judgments in a concise, concentrated form. This is apparently due to the fact that the work was written on the basis of lectures he gave in France.

So, the first conclusion that Plekhanov makes:

“The tendency towards art for art’s sake arises where there is a discord between artists and the social environment around them.” (5)

This conclusion is not unfounded; it is confirmed by the example of Pushkin, and then by the example of French literature. It would seem that the French romantics were not at odds with their environment. Where then did the sentiment expressed by Gautier come from:

“I will with great joy give up my rights as a Frenchman and a citizen in order to see an authentic painting by Raphael or a naked beauty.” (6)

Plekhanov proves that the romantics could not help but dissociate themselves from the bourgeoisie, who thought only about how to earn more and invest their earnings better. Romantics treated them with contempt. Another thing is that such a demarcation did not threaten the power of these “bourgeois” in any way, since the departure of an artist into “pure art” does not pose anything dangerous for the authorities.

“When the bourgeoisie took a dominant position in society, and when its life was no longer warmed by the fire of the liberation struggle, then the new art was left with one thing: the idealization of the negation of the bourgeois way of life.” (7)

But that's not all. Clarifying the previous conclusion about artists’ inclination towards “art for art’s sake,” Plekhanov adds:

“The tendency of artists and people keenly interested in artistic creativity to art for art’s sake arises out of a hopeless discord between them and the social environment around them.” (8)

This explains why contempt for the bourgeoisie is not expressed in the desire to overthrow their power, but causes them to withdraw into “pure” art. Feeling the impossibility of practically changing anything, artists are looking for ways to realize their ideas in art for art’s sake. At least establish justice in imaginary worlds, if this is impossible in the real world. This reason for going into “pure art” has not lost any of its relevance even now.

But what reason brings to life a different view of art? Here is how Plekhanov answers this question:

“... the so-called utilitarian view of art, i.e., the tendency to give its works the meaning of a verdict on the phenomena of life and the joyful readiness that always accompanies it to participate in social battles, arises and strengthens where there is mutual sympathy between a significant part of society and people, more or less actively interested in artistic creativity.” (9)

But there is a difference between when such relationships develop spontaneously between the artist and society, as, for example, during revolutions, and when political power tries to impose such relationships.

And Plekhanov clarifies: “... any given political power always prefers a utilitarian view of art, of course, since it pays attention to this subject.” (10)

But it is interesting that “... a utilitarian view of art gets along just as well with a conservative mood as with a revolutionary one. The inclination towards such a view necessarily presupposes only one condition: a living and active interest in a known, no matter what kind of social order or social ideal, and it disappears wherever this interest disappears for one reason or another.” (eleven)

And here is another very interesting conclusion that clarifies many things even today:

“The muses of artists ... would begin, having become state muses, to reveal the most obvious signs of decline and would lose extremely much in their truthfulness, strength and attractiveness.” (12)

Next, Plekhanov touches on another complex but important topic. We are talking about the ideological content of a work of art. He is convinced that ultimately the value of any work is determined by its content, that is, the value of the idea contained in the work. "… When false idea is placed at the basis of a work of art, it introduces into it such internal contradictions from which its aesthetic dignity inevitably suffers.” (13)

Here Plekhanov gives the example of one of Hamsun’s plays, where the main character is inspired by the idea of ​​a superman, but as a result the play itself did not work out, because: “Only something that promotes communication between people can give true inspiration to an artist. The possible limits of such communication are determined not by the artist, but by the height of culture achieved by the social whole to which he belongs.” (14)

It is worth noting here that when you come across a work as densely written as this work Plekhanov, it’s difficult to get your word in, but you just want to quote and quote, risking being accused of simply taking notes. What can we do, and our capabilities are determined by the height of culture.

But let's continue. In the same work, Plekhanov argues with Lunacharsky, who accused him of the fact that if you believe Plekhanov, then there is no absolute ideal of beauty at all, since “... it is always rich in quite definite, and not at all absolute, i.e., not unconditional content.” . (15)

To this Plekhanov replies: “... if there is no absolute criterion of beauty, if all criteria are relative, this does not mean that we are deprived of any objective opportunity to judge whether a given artistic plan is well executed.” (16)

How then to evaluate works? What can serve as a yardstick, independent of existing social relations, that can measure the quality of a work of art? Plekhanov gives the following answer: “The more the execution corresponds to the plan, or, to use a more general expression, the more the form of a work of art corresponds to its idea, the more successful it is. Here’s an objective measure for you.” (17)

In this work, we wanted not so much to argue with Plekhanov, since such an argument would require having different convictions, but to once again be convinced of the strength and vitality of the Marxist method in any science, including aesthetics. This strength and this vitality exist because Marxism stands on the solid foundation of a really existing world with all its contradictions and zigzags of development.

Not the construction of certain spiritual systems that exist only in the imagination of their creators and are therefore unviable, but the study of the laws of social and economic development and, on this basis, the choice of a path always from several possible options. The more known facts about the previous path, the easier and more correct the choice. This is precisely what I would like to learn from Plekhanov. Actually, that’s why we turned to his work.

Sources:
1. G. V. Plekhanov. Collected Works, vol.5.
2. V.I.Lenin. Selected works in three volumes. vol.3, M., Politizdat, 1976, p. 457.
3. G. I. Kunitsyn. Universality in literature. M., Soviet writer, 1980, p. 243
4. G. V. Plekhanov. Collected Works, vol. 5., p. 686
5. Ibid., p.693
6. Ibid., p.694
7. Ibid., p.696
8. Ibid., p.698
9. Ibid., p.699
10. Ibid., p.700
11. Ibid., p.703
12. Ibid., p.703
13. Ibid., p.717
14. Ibid., p.716
15. Ibid., p.708
16. Ibid., p.745
17. Ibid., p.746

IV.32. Plekhanov G.V.

Art and social life

Plekhanov Georgy Valentinovich(1856–1918) – founder of Marxism in Russia, politician, consistent opponent of V.I. Lenin and the Bolsheviks, social philosopher, esthetician, art theorist.

Plekhanov's views on art flowed from his materialist understanding of history. Viewing art as social phenomenon, Plekhanov argued with the definition of art given by Tolstoy, who saw in art only emotional content (with art “people convey their feelings to each other”). Plekhanov argued that art expresses both people's feelings and thoughts.

By this he emphasized the ideological nature of art; he saw in the imagery of art the specificity of its ideological nature. From the point of view of dialectical materialism, literature and art are “ideologies,” specific forms of social consciousness, Plekhanov believed.

The question of the relationship of art to social life has always played a very important role in all literature that has reached a certain degree of development. Most often it was and is being resolved in two directly opposite senses.

Some said and say: man is not for the Sabbath, but the Sabbath is for man; not society for the artist, but the artist for society. Art should contribute to the development of human consciousness and the improvement of the social order.

Others strongly reject this view. In their opinion, art itself is target, turn it into a remedy to achieve some extraneous, even the most noble goals, means to humiliate the dignity of a work of art.

The first of these two views found vivid expression in our advanced literature of the 60s. Not to mention Pisarev, who in his extreme one-sidedness brought it almost to the point of caricature, one can recall Chernyshevsky and Dobrolyubov as the most thorough defenders of this view in the criticism of that time. In one of his first critical articles, Chernyshevsky wrote:

“‘Art for art’s sake’ is as strange a thought in our time as ‘wealth for riches’, ‘science for science’, etc.”<…>

The opposite view of the task of artistic creativity had a powerful defender in the person of Pushkin. The people, demanding from the poet that he improve social morals with his songs, hear from him a contemptuous, one might say, rude rebuke:

Go away! What's the matter

The peaceful poet before you?

Pushkin formulates the poet’s tasks as follows. words:

Not for everyday worries,

Not for gain, not for battles,

We were born to inspire

For sweet sounds and prayers!

Here we have before us the so-called theory of art for art's sake in its most vivid formulation.

Which of these two directly opposite views on the task of art can be considered correct?<…>

If the artists of a given country at a given time shun “everyday excitement and battles,” and at other times, on the contrary, greedily strive for both battles and the excitement inevitably associated with them, then this is not because someone outside is prescribing for them various duties (“must”) in different eras, but because under some social conditions they are dominated by one mood, and under others by another. This means that a correct attitude towards a subject requires us to look at it not from the point of view of what should have been, but from the point of view of what was and what is. In view of this, we will pose the question this way:

What are the most important of those social conditions under which artists and people with a keen interest in artistic creativity develop and strengthen a penchant for art for art’s sake?

When we get closer to solving this question, then it will not be difficult for us to solve another one, closely related to it and no less interest Ask:

What are the most important of those social conditions under which the so-called utilitarian view of art arises and strengthens among artists and people who are keenly interested in artistic creativity, that is, the tendency to give its works “the meaning of a verdict on the phenomena of life”? <…>

We are faced with the following conclusion:

The tendency towards art for art's sake arises where there is a discord between artists and the social environment around them.<…>

Romantics. were at odds with the bourgeois society around them. True, in this discord there was nothing dangerous for bourgeois social relations. The romantic circles included young bourgeois who had nothing against these relationships, but at the same time were outraged by the dirt, boredom and vulgarity of bourgeois existence. The new art, which they were so keen on, was for them a refuge from this dirt, boredom and vulgarity. IN last years restoration and in the first half of the reign of Louis Philippe, that is, during the best time of romanticism, it was all the more difficult for French youth to get used to bourgeois dirt, prose and boredom, because shortly before that France experienced the terrible storms of the great revolution and the Napoleonic era, which deeply shook up everything human passions. When the bourgeoisie took a dominant position in society and when its life was no longer warmed by the fire of the liberation struggle, then only one thing remained for the new art: idealization of the negation of the bourgeois way of life. Romantic art was such an idealization. The Romantics tried to express their negative attitude towards bourgeois moderation and neatness not only in their artistic works, but even in their appearance.<…>Fantastic costumes, like long hair, served as a means for young romantics to oppose themselves to the hated bourgeois.

Given this attitude of the young romantics towards the bourgeoisie, they could not help but be indignant at the thought of “useful art.” To make art useful meant, in their eyes, to make it serve the very bourgeois whom they so deeply despised.<…>The Parnassians and the first French realists (Goncourt, Flaubert, etc.) also infinitely despised the bourgeois society that surrounded them. They, too, constantly vilified the “bourgeois” they hated. If they published their works, then, according to them, it was not at all for the general reading public, but only for a select few, “for unknown friends,” as Flaubert puts it in one of his letters. They were of the opinion that only a writer without great talent could please any wide reading public.<…>

Now, I think I can supplement my previous conclusion and say this:

The tendency of artists and people keenly interested in artistic creativity to art for art's sake arises out of a hopeless discord between them and the social environment around them.

That's not all. An example of our “people of the 60s”, who firmly believed in the near triumph of reason. shows us that the so-called utilitarian view of art, that is, the tendency to give its works the meaning of a verdict on the phenomena of life and the joyful readiness to participate in social battles that always accompanies it, arises and strengthens where there is mutual sympathy between a significant part of society and people, more or less actively interested in artistic creativity. <…>

To put an end to this side of the question, I will add that any given political power always prefers a utilitarian view of art, of course, insofar as it pays attention to this subject. Yes, it is understandable: it is in her interests to direct all ideologies to serve the cause that she herself serves. And since political power, which is sometimes revolutionary, is more often conservative or even completely reactionary, it is already clear from this that one should not think that the utilitarian view of art is shared mainly by revolutionaries or, in general, by people of progressive thought. The history of Russian literature very clearly shows that our guardians were not at all averse to it.<…>

Those servants of Nicholas I looked at art in exactly the same way, for whom, according to the unofficial position, it was impossible to do without some kind of view of art. You remember that Benckendorff tried to direct Pushkin on the path of truth. Ostrovsky was not spared the concerns of his superiors. When in March 1850 his comedy “Our People – Let’s Be Numbered” appeared in print and when some enlightened lovers of literature... and trade began to fear that it might offend the merchants, then the Minister of Public Education (Prince P.A. Shirinsky-Shikhmatov ) ordered the trustee of the Moscow educational district to invite an aspiring playwright to his place and “to convince him that the noble and useful goal of talent should consist not only in a lively depiction of the funny and bad, but also in its fair censure, not only in caricature, but also in the dissemination of the highest moral feeling: therefore, in contrast to vice with virtue, and pictures of the ridiculous and criminal - such thoughts and deeds that elevate the soul; finally, in the affirmation of that belief, so important for the life of public and private, that crime finds a worthy punishment still on earth."

Emperor Nikolai Pavlovich himself looked at the task of art primarily from a moral point of view.<…>

And do not think that the Russian rulers were any exception in this case. No, such a typical representative of absolutism as Louis XIV was in France, was no less firmly convinced that art cannot serve as an end in itself, but must promote moral education of people. And all the literature, all the art of the famous century Louis XIV were thoroughly imbued with this conviction. Likewise, Napoleon I would have looked at the theory of art for art’s sake as one of the harmful inventions of unpleasant “ideologists.” He also wanted literature and art to serve moral purposes. And he succeeded to a large extent, since, for example, most of the paintings exhibited at periodic exhibitions of that time (“Salons”) were devoted to depicting the military exploits of the consulate and the empire.<…>

But let’s leave government “spheres”. Among the French writers of the Second Empire there are people who rejected the theory of art for art's sake not at all for any progressive reasons. Thus, Alexandre Dumas the son categorically stated that the words “art for art’s sake” have no meaning.<…>

From all this it follows with complete conviction that the utilitarian view of art gets along just as well with a conservative mood as with a revolutionary one. The inclination towards such a view necessarily presupposes only one condition: a living and active interest in what is known, no matter which one, social order or social ideal, and it disappears wherever this interest disappears for one reason or another.

Like all questions of social life and social thought, this question does not admit of an unconditional solution. It all depends on the conditions of time and place. Let us remember Nicholas I and his servants. They wanted to make of Pushkin, Ostrovsky and other contemporary artists servants of morality, as the gendarme corps understood it. Let us assume for a moment that they managed to carry out this firm intention. What was supposed to come out of this? It's not difficult to answer. The muses of artists who submitted to their influence would, having become state muses, show the most obvious signs of decline and would lose extremely much in their truthfulness, strength and attractiveness.

Pushkin’s poem “To the Slanderers of Russia” cannot at all be considered one of his best poetic creations. Ostrovsky’s play “Don’t Get in Your Own Sleigh,” favorably recognized as a “useful lesson,” is also God knows how successful. Meanwhile, Ostrovsky took barely a few steps in it towards the ideal that the Benckendorffs sought to realize. and others, similar to them, supporters of useful art.<…>

Works of art are always something they say because they are always doing something express. Of course, they “tell” in their own special “way.” An artist expresses his idea with images, while a publicist proves his idea with the help of logical conclusions. And if the writer uses logical arguments instead of images, or if he comes up with images to prove famous topic, then he is not an artist, but a publicist, even though he wrote not studies and articles, but novels, stories or theatrical plays. All this is true. But from all this it does not at all follow that in a work of art the idea does not matter. I will say more: there cannot be a work of art devoid of ideological content. Even those works whose authors value only the form and do not care about the content still express a certain idea in one way or another.<…>

But if there is no work of art that is completely devoid of ideological content, then not every idea can be expressed in a work of art. Ruskin says it well: a girl can sing about lost love, but a miser cannot sing about lost money. And he rightly notes that the dignity of a work of art is determined by the height of the mood it expresses.<…>Otherwise it can not be. Art is one of the means of spiritual communication between people. And the higher the feeling expressed by a given work of art, the more conveniently, other things being equal, this work can play its role as the indicated means. Why shouldn't a miser sing about lost money? Very simply: because if he sang about his loss, then his song would not touch anyone, that is, it could not serve as a means of communication between him and other people.

They may point to war songs and ask me: is war really a means of communication between people? I will answer this that military poetry, expressing hatred of the enemy, at the same time glorifies the selflessness of soldiers - their willingness to die for their homeland, for their state, etc. It is to the extent that it expresses such readiness, it serves as a means of communication between people within those boundaries (tribe, community, state), the breadth of which is determined by the level of cultural development achieved by humanity or, more accurately, by a given part of it...<…>

Even Belinsky, who quite rightly asserted in last period of his literary activity, which is “pure, detached, unconditional, or, as philosophers say, absolute, art has never happened anywhere,” admitted, however, that the works of painting of the Italian school of the 16th century to a certain extent approached the ideal of absolute art, since they were the creation of an era during which “art was the main interest, exclusively occupying the educated part of society.” For example, he pointed to Raphael's Madonna. But Italian schools The 16th century completed a long process of struggle between the earthly ideal and the Christian monastic ideal. And no matter how exceptional the interest of the most educated part of society of the 16th century in art was, it is undeniable that Raphael’s Madonnas are one of the most characteristic artistic expressions of the victory of the earthly ideal over the Christian monastic one.<…>

The ideal of beauty that dominates at a given time in a given society - or in a given class of society - is rooted partly in the biological conditions of the development of the human race, which, among other things, create racial characteristics, and partly in the historical conditions of the emergence and existence of this society or this class . And that is precisely why it is always very rich in quite definite and not at all absolute, that is, not unconditional, content. Who worships " pure beauty”, he by this does not at all make himself independent of those biological and socio-historical conditions that determined his aesthetic taste, but only more or less consciously turns a blind eye to these conditions. This was the case, by the way, with the romantics.<…>

The general rule was that, while rebelling against bourgeois vulgarity, the romantics at the same time were very unfriendly to socialist systems that pointed to the need for social reform. The Romantics wanted to change social mores without changing anything in the social structure. It goes without saying that this is completely impossible. Therefore, the uprising of the romantics against the “bourgeois” led to it. few practical consequences. But its practical futility had important literary consequences. She reported romantic heroes that character of stiltedness and fictionality, which ultimately led to the collapse of the school. The stilted and fictitious character of the heroes cannot in any way be recognized as the merit of a work of art, therefore, next to the above We should now add a well-known minus as a plus: if romantic works of art gained a lot thanks to the rebellion of their authors against the “bourgeois,” then, on the other hand, they lost a lot due to the practical meaninglessness of this revolt.

Already the first French realists made every effort to eliminate the main drawback romantic works: the fictional, stilted nature of their heroes. There is not a trace of romantic fiction and stiltedness in Flaubert's novels. The first realists continue to rebel against the “bourgeois,” but they rebel against them in a different way. They do not contrast unprecedented heroes with bourgeois vulgarities, but try to make vulgarities the subject of an artistically faithful depiction.<…>

Ecclesiastes says excellently: “By oppressing others, the wise become foolish.” The discovery by bourgeois ideologists of the secret of the struggle between their class and the proletariat led to the fact that they gradually lost the ability to calmly scientific research social phenomena. And this greatly reduced the intrinsic value of their more or less scientific works. If previously bourgeois political economy could put forward such a giant of scientific thought as David Ricardo, now talkative dwarfs like Frederic Bastiat began to set the tone among its representatives. In philosophy, an idealistic reaction began to take hold more and more, the essence of which lies in the conservative desire to reconcile the successes of modern natural science with the old religious tradition, or, to put it more precisely, to reconcile the chapel with the laboratory. Art did not escape the common fate. We will see to what ridiculous absurdities the influence of the current idealistic reaction has driven some of the newest painters. Now for now I will say the following.

The conservative and partly even reactionary way of thinking of the first realists did not prevent them from thoroughly studying their environment and creating things that were very valuable artistically. But there is no doubt that he greatly narrowed their field of vision. By turning hostilely away from the great liberation movement of their time, they thereby excluded from the number of “mastodons” and “crocodiles” they observed the most interesting specimens, those with the richest inner life. Their objective attitude towards the environment they studied meant, in fact, a lack of sympathy for it. And, of course, they could not sympathize with the fact that, with their conservatism, only one thing was accessible to their observation: “petty thoughts” and “petty passions” born in the “unclean mud” of everyday bourgeois existence. But this lack of sympathy for objects observed and invented quite soon caused and was bound to cause a decline in interest in him. Naturalism, to which they laid the first foundation with their remarkable works, soon found itself, as Huysmans put it, in “a stupid alley, a tunnel with a blocked exit.” He could, as Huysmans put it, make everything his subject, up to and including syphilis. But the modern labor movement remained inaccessible to him.<…>This method was closely connected with the point of view of that materialism, which Marx called natural science and which does not understand that actions, inclinations, tastes and habits of thought public people cannot find a sufficient explanation for themselves in physiology or pathology, since they are determined social relations. By staying true to this method, artists could study and depict their "mastodons" and "crocodiles" as individuals rather than as members of a great whole. This is what Huysmans felt when he said that naturalism had found itself in a blind alley and that he had no choice but to talk once again about the love affair of the first wine merchant he met with the first petty shopkeeper he met. Narratives of such relationships could be of interest only if they shed light on a certain aspect of social relations, as was the case in Russian realism. But the French realists lacked public interest. As a result, the depiction of “the love affair of the first wine merchant he met with the first petty shopkeeper he met” eventually became uninteresting, boring and even simply disgusting.<…>

An artist who has become a mystic does not neglect the ideological content, but only gives it a unique character. Mysticism is also an idea, but only dark, formless, like fog, in mortal enmity with reason. The mystic is not averse to not only telling, but even proving. Only he tells something “not done”, and in his evidence he takes the denial of common sense as the starting point. But when artists become blind to the most important social trends of their time, then the nature of the ideas they express in their works greatly decreases in their intrinsic value. And these latter inevitably suffer from this.<…>

The tendency towards art for art's sake appears and is strengthened where there is a hopeless discord between people involved in art and the social environment around them. This discord has a beneficial effect on artistic creativity to the very extent that it helps artists rise above their environment. This was the case with Pushkin in the Nicholas era. This was the case with the Romantics, the Parnassians and the first realists in France. By multiplying the number of examples, it would be possible to prove that this has always been the case where the indicated discord existed. But, rebelling against the vulgar mores of the social environment around them, the romantics, Parnassians and realists had nothing against the social relations in which these vulgar mores were rooted. On the contrary, while cursing the “bourgeois,” they valued the bourgeois system—at first instinctively, and then with full consciousness. And the more the liberation movement directed against the bourgeois system intensified in modern Europe, the more conscious the attachment to this system of the French supporters of art for art's sake became. And the more conscious their attachment became, the less they could remain indifferent to the ideological content of their works. But their blindness to the new trend, aimed at renewing all social life, made their views erroneous, narrow, one-sided and lowered the quality of the ideas that were expressed in their works. The natural result of this was the hopeless situation of French realism, which gave rise to decadent hobbies and a tendency towards mysticism in writers who themselves had once gone through the realistic (naturalistic) school.<…>

When a given class lives by the exploitation of another class below it on the economic ladder, and when it has achieved complete dominance in society, then go ahead- means for this class go down. This is the solution to what is at first glance incomprehensible and perhaps even incredible phenomenon that in economically backward countries the ideology of the ruling classes is often much higher than in advanced ones.

Now Russia has already reached that height of economic development at which supporters of the theory of art for art's sake become conscious defenders of a social order based on the exploitation of one class by another. That’s why we now say a lot of socially reactionary nonsense in the name of “absolute autonomy of art.”

In the book: Plekhanov G.V.

Selected philosophical works: In 5 volumes. T. 5. M., 1958.

INSTITUTE OF K. MARX AND F. ENGELS

Workers of all countries, unite!

G. V. PLEKHANOV

ESSAYS

STATE PUBLISHING HOUSE MOSCOW

Art and social life 1)
("Contemporary", 1912, NoNo 11, 12 and 1913, No 1)

1) The work offered to the attention of readers is a reworking of the “abstract” that I read in Russian in November of this year in Liege and Paris. Therefore, to a certain extent, she retained the form of reading. At the end of its second part, the objections publicly made to me in Paris by Mr. Lunacharsky on the question of the criterion of beauty will be considered. Having answered them orally in a timely manner, I consider it useful to dwell on them in print.

I

The question of the relationship of art to social life has always played a very important role in all literature that has reached a certain degree of development. Most often, it was and is being resolved in two, directly opposite, senses. Some said and say: man is not for the Sabbath, but the Sabbath is for man; not society for the artist, but the artist for society. Art should contribute to the development of human consciousness and the improvement of the social order. Others strongly reject this view. In their opinion, art in itself is a goal; to turn it into a means to achieve some extraneous, even the most noble goals, means to humiliate the dignity of a work of art. The first of these two views found clear expression in our advanced literature of the 60s. Not to mention Pisarev, who, in his extreme one-sidedness, brought it almost to the point of caricature, one can recall Chernyshevsky and Dobrolyubov as the most thorough defenders of this view in the criticism of that time. In one of his first critical articles, Chernyshevsky wrote: “Art for art’s sake” is a thought as strange in our time as “wealth for wealth,” “science for science,” etc. All human affairs should serve to benefit man , if they want to be not an empty and idle occupation: wealth exists in order for a person to use it, science in order to be a leader of a person, art should also serve for some significant benefit, and not for fruitless pleasure." According to Chernyshevsky , the meaning of art, and in particular “the most serious of them” - poetry, is determined by the mass of knowledge that they disseminate in society; he says: “Art or, better said, poetry (poetry alone, because there are very few other arts do in this regard) disseminates a huge amount of information among the masses of readers and, more importantly, familiarity with the concepts developed by science - this is the great significance of poetry for life" (N. G. Chernyshevsky, Complete collection. works., vol. I., pp. 33--34.). The same idea is expressed in his famous dissertation “Aesthetic Relations of Art to Reality.” According to her seventeenth thesis, art not only reproduces life, but also explains it; very often his works “have the meaning of a verdict on the phenomena of life.” In the eyes of Chernyshevsky and his student Dobrolyubov, the main meaning of art lay in the reproduction of life and in pronouncing a verdict on its phenomena (This look was partly repetition, partly further development the view developed by Belinsky in the last years of his life. In the article "A Look at Russian Literature of 1847" Belinsky wrote: “The highest and most sacred interest of society is its own well-being, equally extended to each of its members. The path to this well-being is consciousness, and art can contribute to consciousness no less than science. Here both science and art are equally necessary, and neither science cannot replace art, nor the art of science." But art can develop people’s consciousness only by pronouncing “sentences on the phenomena of life.” This is how Chernyshevsky’s dissertation is connected with Belinsky’s latest look at Russian literature.). And not only literary critics and art theorists. It was not for nothing that Nekrasov called his muse the muse of “revenge and sadness.” In one of his poems, a citizen, addressing the poet, says: And you, poet, the chosen one of heaven, the Herald of age-old truths! Do not believe that the one who does not have bread is not worth your prophetic strings!
Do not believe that people have fallen altogether: God has not died in the souls of people,
And the cry from the believing breast will always be available to her! Be a citizen! Serving art, live for the good of your neighbor, subordinating your genius to the feeling of Universal Love. With these words, citizen Nekrasov expressed his own understanding of the task of art. The most prominent figures in the field of plastic arts, for example, in painting, understood this task in exactly the same way at that time. Perov and Kramskoy sought, like Nekrasov, to be “citizens” by serving art; they, like Him, pronounced “a verdict on the phenomena of life” with their works (Kramsky’s letter to V.V. Stasov from Menton dated April 30, 1884 testifies to the strong influence on him of the views of Belinsky, Gogol, Fedotov, Ivanov, Chernyshevsky, Dobrolyubov , Perova ("Ivan Nikolaevich Kramskoy, his life, correspondence and art-critical articles", St. Petersburg. 1888, p. 487). It should be noted, however, that the sentences about the phenomena of life found in the critical articles of I. N. Kramskoy , are far inferior in their clarity to those sentences that we find, for example, in G.I. Uspensky, not to mention Chernyshevsky and Dobrolyubov.). The opposite view of the task of artistic creativity had a powerful defender in the person of Pushkin of the Nicholas era. Everyone knows, of course, such of his poems as “Mob” and “To the Poet”. The people, demanding from the poet that he improve social morals with his songs, hear from him a contemptuous, one might say, rude rebuke: Go away! What does the Peaceful Poet have to do with you? Feel free to turn to stone in debauchery: The voice of the lyre will not revive you! You are disgusting to the soul, like coffins; For your stupidity and malice Until now you have had whips, prisons, axes - Enough for you, crazy slaves! Pushkin’s view of the poet’s task is outlined in the following, so often repeated, words: Not for everyday worries, Not for self-interest, not for battles, We were born for inspiration, For sweet sounds and prayers! Here we have before us the so-called theory of art for art's sake in its most vivid formulation. It was not without reason that opponents of the literary movement of the 60s so readily and so often referred to Pushkin. Which of these two directly opposite views on the task of art can be considered correct? In approaching this question, it is necessary to note, first of all, that it is poorly formulated. It, like all questions like it, cannot be looked at from the point of view of “duty”. If the artists of a given country at a given time shun “everyday excitement and battles,” and at other times, on the contrary, greedily strive for both battles and the excitement inevitably associated with it, then this is not because someone outside is prescribing for them various duties (“must”) in different eras, but because under some social conditions they are dominated by one mood, and under others by another. This means that a correct attitude towards a subject requires us to look at it not from the point of view of what should have been, but from the point of view of what was and what is. In view of this, we pose the question this way: What are the most important of those social conditions under which the inclination towards art for art’s sake arises and strengthens among artists and among people who are keenly interested in artistic creativity? When we. Let us get closer to solving this question, then it will not be difficult for us to solve another, closely related and no less interesting question: What are the most important of those social conditions under which artists and people keenly interested in artistic creativity arise and strengthen the so-called utilitarian view of art, that is, the tendency to give its works “the meaning of a verdict on the phenomena of life”? The first of these two questions forces us to remember Pushkin again. There was a time when he did not defend theories of art for art's sake. There was a time when he did not avoid battles, but sought them. This was the case in the era of Alexander I. Then he did not think that the “people” should be content with whips, dungeons and axes. On the contrary, he exclaimed indignantly then in his ode “Liberty”: Alas! Wherever I look, there are whips everywhere, glands everywhere, the disastrous shame of the laws, weak tears of captivity; Unjust power everywhere In the thick darkness of prejudice, etc. And then his mood changed radically. In the era of Nicholas I, he adopted the theory of art for art's sake. What caused this huge change in his mood? The beginning of the reign of Nicholas 1 was marked by the disaster of December 14, which had a huge impact both on the further course of development of our “society” and on the personal fate of Pushkin. In the face defeated The most educated and progressive representatives of the then “society” left the stage of the “Decembrists”. This could not but lead to a significant decrease in his moral and mental level. “No matter how young I was,” says Herzen, “but I remember how clearly high society fell and became dirtier, more servile with the accession of Nicholas. Aristocratic independence, the guards prowess of Alexander’s times - all this disappeared in 1826.” It was hard to live in such a sensitive and smart person. “All around there was wilderness, silence,” says the same Herzen in another article, “everything was unresponsive, inhuman, hopeless and, at the same time, extremely flat, stupid and petty. The gaze, seeking sympathy, met a lackey’s threat or fear, they turned away from it or insulted him." In Pushkin's letters dating back to the time when the poems "Mob" and "To the Poet" were written, there are constant complaints about the boredom and vulgarity of both of our capitals. But he suffered not only from the vulgarity of the society around him. His relationship with the “ruling spheres” also spoiled a lot of blood for him. The touching legend that in 1826 Nicholas I generously “forgave” Pushkin his political “mistakes of youth” and even became his generous patron is widely spread among us. But that was not the case at all. Nikolai and his right hand in matters of this kind, the chief of gendarmes A.H. Benckendorff, did not “forgive” Pushkin anything, and their “patronage” for him was expressed for him in a long series of unbearable humiliations. In 1827, Benckendorff reported to Nikolai: “Pushkin, after a meeting with me, spoke with delight in an English club about Your Majesty and forced the people who dined with him to drink Your Majesty’s health. He is still a decent scoundrel, but if you can direct his pen and his speech, then it will be beneficial." The last words of this passage reveal to us the secret of the “patronage” provided to Pushkin. They wanted to make him a singer of the existing order of things. Nicholas I and Benckendorff set themselves the task of directing his previously violent muse onto the path of official morality. When, after Pushkin’s death, Field Marshal Paskevich wrote to Nikolai: “I feel sorry for Pushkin as a writer,” he answered him: “I completely share your opinion, and about him (that is, about Pushkin, and not about opinion. G. P.) one can rightly say that it mourns the future, not the past" (Shchegolev, "Pushkin." Essays, St. Petersburg, 1912, p. 357.). This means that the unforgettable emperor valued the deceased poet not for the great things that he wrote during his short life, but for what he could have written with proper police supervision and guidance. Nikolai expected from him “patriotic” works in the spirit of the Puppeteer’s play “The Hand of the Almighty Saved the Fatherland.” Even the unearthly poet V. A. Zhukovsky, who was a very good courtier, tried to reason with him and instill in him respect for morality. In a letter dated April 12, 1826, he said: “Our youths (that is, the entire maturing generation), with a poor upbringing that does not give them any support for life, became acquainted with your violent thoughts, dressed in the charm of poetry; you have already harmed many incurable harm - it should make you tremble. Talent is nothing. The main thing: moral greatness..." (Shchegolev, ibid., p. 241.). You will agree that, being in such a position, bearing the chain of such guardianship and listening to such edifications, it was quite permissible to hate “moral greatness”, to be disgusted with all the “benefits” that art can bring, and to exclaim at the address of advisers and patrons : Go away - what does the peaceful Poet have to do with you? In other words: being in such a position, it was quite natural for Pushkin to become a supporter of the theory of art for art’s sake and to say to the poet in his own person: You are a king: live alone, along a free path, Go where your free mind takes you, Improving the fruits of your favorite thoughts, Without demanding rewards for a noble feat. D.I. Pisarev would object to me that Pushkin’s poet addresses these harsh words not to patrons, but to “the people.” But the real people were completely out of sight of the literature of that time. The word “people” in Pushkin has the same meaning as the word “crowd”, which is often used by him. And this last, of course, does not apply to the working masses. In his "Gypsies" Pushkin characterizes the inhabitants of stuffy cities: they are ashamed of Love, they drive away thoughts, they trade by my own will , They bow their heads before idols and ask for money and chains. It is difficult to imagine that this characteristic applies, for example, to urban artisans. If all this is correct, then the following conclusion emerges before us: The tendency towards art for art’s sake arises where there is a discord between artists and the social environment around them. One can say, of course, that Pushkin’s example is not sufficient to substantiate such a conclusion. I will not argue or contradict. I will give other examples, borrowing them from the history of French literature, that is, the literature of that country, the intellectual currents of which, at least until half of the last century, met with the widest sympathy throughout the entire European continent. The French romantics contemporary to Pushkin were also, with few exceptions, ardent supporters of art for art's sake. Perhaps the most consistent among them, Théophile Gautier, treated the defenders of the utilitarian view of art this way: “No, fools, no, goiter cretins, you cannot make gelatin soup from a book, or a pair of boots without seams from a novel... I swear by the guts of all there are no fathers of the future, past and present time, and two hundred thousand times no... I am one of those who consider the superfluous necessary; my love for things and people is inversely proportional to the services that they can provide" (Preface to the novel M- lle de Maupin.). The same Gautier, in a biographical note about Baudelaire, highly praised the author of “Fleurs du mal” for the fact that he defended “the absolute autonomy of art and did not allow poetry to have another goal other than itself, and another task other than the task of evoking in the soul the reader has a feeling of beauty in the absolute sense of the word" ("l"autonomie absolue de l"art et qu"il n"admettait pas que la poésie eût d"autre but qu"elle même et d"autre mission à remplir que d"exciter dans l "âme du lecteur la new and political ideas, is clear from his following statement: How poorly the “idea of ​​beauty” coexisted in Gautier’s mind with social and political ideas is clear from his following statement: “I will refuse with great joy (très joyeusement) from my rights as a Frenchman and a citizen to see a genuine painting by Raphael or a naked beauty." There is nowhere to go further than this. Meanwhile, all the Parnassians (les parnassiens) would probably agree with Gautier, at least some of them would have done, maybe perhaps some reservations about the too paradoxical form in which he expressed, especially in his younger years, the demand for “absolute autonomy of art.” Where did this mood come from among the French romantics and the Parnassians? Were they also at odds with the society around them? In 1857, T. Gautier, in an article about the resumption of de Vigny’s play “Chatterton” on the stage of the Théâtre Franèais, recalled its first performance, which took place on February 12, 1835. And then he said the following: “The orchestra, before which Chatterton performed, was crowded with pale, long-haired young men who firmly believed that there was no other worthy occupation than writing poetry or paintings... and who looked at the “bourgeois” with that contempt that can hardly be compared with the contempt of the Heidelberg and Jena Fuchs for the philistines" ( Histoire du romanticisme, pp. 153--154.). Who were these despicable "bourgeois"? “They included almost everyone,” Gautier replies, “bankers, brokers, notaries, merchants, shopkeepers, etc. - in a word, everyone who did not belong to the mysterious cénacle (i.e., to the romantic circle. G.P.) and who earned their livelihood in a prosaic way" (Ibid, p. 154.). And here is another evidence. In a commentary to one of his "Odes funambulesques" Theodore de Banville admits that he also experienced this hatred of the "bourgeois" At the same time, he also explains who the Romantics actually called that: in the language of the Romantics, the word bourgeois “meant a person who worships only the five-franc coin, who has no other ideal than preserving his skin, and who loves a sentimental novel in poetry, and in the plastic arts - lithograph" (Les odes funambulesques. Paris 1858, p. p. 294--295.). Recalling this, de Banville asked his readers not to be surprised that in his "Odes funambulesques" - which, note this, appeared already at the very latest the period of romanticism - people are treated like the last scoundrels, guilty only of the fact that they led a bourgeois lifestyle and did not bow to romantic geniuses.
This evidence shows quite convincingly that the romantics were, in fact, at odds with the bourgeois society around them. True, in this discord there was nothing dangerous for bourgeois social relations. The romantic circles included young bourgeois who had nothing against these relationships, but at the same time were outraged by the dirt, boredom and vulgarity of bourgeois existence. The new art, which they were so keen on, was for them a refuge from this dirt, boredom and vulgarity. In the last years of the restoration and in the first half of the reign of Louis Philippe, that is, in the best time of romanticism, it was all the more difficult for French youth to get used to bourgeois dirt, prose and boredom, since shortly before that France had experienced the terrible storms of the great revolution and the Napoleonic era, deeply stirring up all human passions (Alfred de Musset characterizes this discord as follows: "Dès lors se formèrent comme deux camps: d"un part les esprits exaltés souffrants; toutes les âmes expansives, qui ont besoin de l"infini, plièrent la tête en pleurant , ils s"enveloppèrent de rêves maladifs, et l"on ne vit plus que de frêles roseaux sur un océan d"amertume. D"une autre part, les hommes de chair restèrent debout, inflexibles, au milieu des jouissances positives, et il ne leur prit d"autre souci que de compter l"argent qu"ils avaient. Ce ne fut qu"un sanglot et un éclat de rire, l"un venant de l"âme, l"autre du corps." (La confession d"un enfant du siècle, p. 10). When the bourgeoisie took a dominant position in society, and when its life was no longer warmed by the fire of the liberation struggle, then the new art was left with one thing: the idealization of the negation of the bourgeois way of life. Romantic art was such an idealization. The Romantics tried to express their negative attitude towards bourgeois moderation and neatness not only in their artistic works, but even in their appearance. We have already heard from Gautier that the young men who filled the stalls at the first performance of Chatterton wore their hair long. Who hasn’t heard of the same Gautier’s red vest, which horrified “decent people”? Fantastic costumes, like long hair, served as a means for young romantics to oppose themselves to the hated bourgeois. The paleness of the face seemed to be the same means: it was, as it were, a protest against bourgeois satiety. Gautier says: “At that time, in the romantic school, the fashion prevailed to have, if possible, a pale, even green, almost cadaverous complexion. This gave the man a fatal, Byronic look, testified that he was tormented by passions and tormented by remorse, made him interesting in the eyes of women (Name work, p. 31.). In Gautier, we read that the romantics had difficulty forgiving Victor Hugo for his decent appearance and in intimate conversations more than once expressed regret about this weakness of the brilliant poet, “which brought him closer to humanity and even to the bourgeoisie” (Ibid., p. 32). In general, it should be noted that the efforts of people to give themselves this or that appearance are always reflected in the social relations of a given era. An interesting sociological study could be written on this topic. Given this attitude of the young romantics towards the bourgeoisie, they could not help but be indignant at the thought of “useful art.” To make art useful meant, in their eyes, to make it serve the very bourgeois whom they so deeply despised. This explains the provocative antics of Gautier that I cited earlier against the preachers of useful art, whom he calls “fools, big-toothed cretins,” etc. This also explains his paradox that the value of people and things is inversely proportional in his eyes to the benefit that they bring. All such antics and paradoxes, in content, are completely equivalent to Pushkin’s: Go away, what does the peaceful Poet care about you? The Parnassians and the first French realists (Goncourt, Flaubert, etc.) also infinitely despised the bourgeois society that surrounded them. They, too, constantly vilified the “bourgeois” they hated. If they published their works, then, according to them, it was not at all for the general reading public, but only for a select few, “for unknown friends,” as Flaubert puts it in one of his letters. They were of the opinion that only a writer without great talent could please any wide reading public. According to Lecomte de Lisle, great success is a sign that the writer is on a low mental level (signe d "infériorité intellectuelle). It is hardly necessary to add that, like the romantics, the Parnassians were unconditional supporters of the theory of art for art's sake. You can It would be possible to give a lot of similar examples. But there is no need for this. We already see with sufficient clarity that the inclination of artists towards art for art's sake naturally arises where they are at odds with the society around them. But it does not hurt to more accurately characterize this discord At the end of the 18th century, in the era immediately preceding the great revolution, advanced French artists were also at odds with the “society” that was then dominant. David and his friends were opponents of the "old order." And this discord was, of course, hopeless in the sense that reconciliation between the old order and them was completely impossible. Moreover, the discord between David and his friends and the old order was incomparably deeper than the discord between the romantics and bourgeois society: David and his friends sought to eliminate the old order; and Théophile Gautier and his like-minded people had nothing, as I have said more than once, against bourgeois social relations and only wanted the bourgeois system to stop giving rise to vulgar bourgeois morals (Theodore de Banville directly says that romantic attacks on the “bourgeois” are completely did not mean the bourgeoisie as a social class (Les Odes funambulesques, Paris 1858, p. 294). This, characteristic of the romantics, conservative rebellion against the “bourgeois”, which by no means extended to the basis of the bourgeois system, was understood by some modern Russians.. . theorists (for example, Mr. Ivanov-Razumnik), as such a struggle against the philistinism, which, in its breadth, significantly exceeds the socio-political struggle of the proletariat with the bourgeoisie. I leave it to the reader to judge how profound such an understanding is. In fact, it shows that people who talk about the history of Russian social thought, unfortunately, do not always take the trouble to first familiarize themselves with the history of thought in Western Europe.). But, rebelling against the old order, David and his friends knew well that behind them, in thick columns, was the third estate, which was soon to become, according to the well-known expression of Abbot Sieyes, everything. Consequently, their sense of discord with the prevailing order was complemented by sympathy for the new society that had formed in the depths of the old and was preparing to replace it. But what we see among the romantics and Parnassians is not at all the same: they do not expect or desire changes in social order in contemporary France. Therefore, their discord with the society around them is completely hopeless (The mood of the German romantics is also distinguished by the same hopeless discord with the social environment that surrounded them, as Brandes perfectly explained in his book Die romantische Schule in Deutschland, which constitutes the second volume of his work Die Hauptströmungen der Literatur des 19 -ten Jahrhunderts.). Our Pushkin did not expect any changes in the Russia of that time. And in the Nicholas era, he, too, perhaps, ceased to desire them. Therefore, his view of public life was tinged with pessimism. Now, I think, I can supplement my previous conclusion and say this: The inclination of artists and people keenly interested in artistic creativity towards art for art’s sake arises out of a hopeless discord between them and their surrounding social environment. That's not all. The example of our “people of the 60s,” who firmly believed in the near triumph of reason, as well as the example of David and his friends, who no less firmly held the same faith, shows us that the so-called utilitarian view of art, i.e., inclination giving his works the meaning of a verdict on the phenomena of life and the joyful readiness that always accompanies it to participate in public battles arises and strengthens where there is mutual sympathy between a significant part of society and people more or less actively interested in artistic creativity. The extent to which this is true is finally proven by this fact.
When the refreshing storm of the February Revolution of 1848 broke out, many of those French artists , who adhered to the theory of art for art's sake, decisively rejected it. Even Baudelaire, whom Gautier later cited as an example of an artist unshakably convinced of the need for the unconditional autonomy of art, immediately began publishing the revolutionary magazine Le salut public. This magazine, however, soon ceased to exist, but back in 1852, in the preface to Pierre Dupont's Chansons, Baudelaire called the theory of art for art's sake childish (puérile) and proclaimed that art should serve social purposes. Only the final victory of the counter-revolution returned Baudelaire and other artists close to him in mood to the “childish” theory of art for art’s sake. One of the future luminaries of Parnassus, Lecomte de Lisle revealed the psychological meaning of this return extremely clearly in the preface to his Poèmes antiques, the first edition of which was published in 1852. There we read from him that poetry will no longer give rise to heroic actions and inspire public virtue, because now, as in all eras of literary decline, its sacred language can only express narrow personal experiences (mesquines impressions personnelles)... and no longer able to teach people (n"est plus apte à enseigner l"homme) (Poèmes antiques Paris 1852, préface, p. VII.). Addressing the poets, Lecomte de Lisle says that they have now been outgrown by the human race, whose teachers they once were (Ibid., p. IX.). Now, according to the future Parnassian, the task of poetry is to “give an ideal life” to someone who no longer has a “real life” (donner la vie idéale à celui qui n"a pas la vie réelle) (Ibid., p. . XI.). These profound words reveal the whole psychological secret of the inclination towards art for art's sake. Later on we will more than once have the opportunity to refer to the just-quoted preface of Lecomte de Lisle. To finish with this side of the question, I will add that any given political power always prefers a utilitarian view of art, of course, since it pays attention to this subject. And this is understandable: it is in its interests to direct all ideologies to serve the cause that it itself serves. And since political power, which is sometimes revolutionary, is more often conservative, or even completely reactionary, then it is already clear from this that one should not think that the utilitarian view of art is shared mainly by revolutionaries or, in general, by people of progressive thought. The history of Russian literature very clearly shows that our guardians were not at all averse to it. Here are some examples. In 1814, the first three parts of the novel by V. T. Narezhny appeared: “Russian Gilblaz, or the adventures of Prince Gavrila Simonovich Chistyakov.” This novel was then banned on the initiative of the Minister of Public Education, Count Razumovsky, who on this occasion expressed the following view on the relationship of fiction to life. “It often happens that the authors of novels, although apparently armed against vices, depict them in such colors or describe them in such detail that they thereby drag young people into vices that it would be more useful not to mention at all. "no matter the literary merit of novels, they can only appear in print when they have a truly moral purpose." As you can see, Razumovsky believed that art cannot serve as an end in itself. Those servants of Nicholas I looked at art in exactly the same way, for whom, according to their official position, it was impossible to do without some kind of view of art. You remember that Benckendorff tried to direct Pushkin on the path of truth. Ostrovsky was not spared the concerns of his superiors. When in March 1850 his comedy appeared in print: “Our people - we will be numbered,” and when some enlightened lovers of literature ... and trade began to fear that it might offend the merchants, then the Minister of Public Education (Prince P. A. Shirinsky-Shikhmatov) ordered the trustee of the Moscow educational district to invite an aspiring playwright and “to convince him that the noble and useful goal of talent should consist not only in a lively depiction of the funny and bad, but also in his fair censure, not only in caricature, but also in the dissemination of the highest moral feeling: therefore, in contrasting vice with virtue, and with pictures of the ridiculous and criminal - such thoughts and deeds that elevate the soul; finally, in the affirmation of that belief, so important for public and private life, that crime finds worthy punishment on earth." Emperor Nikolai Pavlovich himself looked at the task of art also primarily from a “moral” point of view. As we know, he shared Benckendorff’s view of the benefits of taming Pushkin. About the play “Don’t Get in Your Own Sleigh,” written in that era when Ostrovsky, having fallen under the influence of the Slavophiles, used to say at merry parties that he, with the help of some of his friends, would “turn back Peter’s cause” - about this, in In a certain sense, a rather edifying play, Nicholas I praised: “Ce n” est pas une pièce, c “est une leèon.” In order not to produce unnecessary examples, I will limit myself to indicating the following two facts. "Moscow Telegraph" by N. Polevoy finally died in the opinion of the Nikolaev government and was banned when it published an unfavorable review of the "patriotic" play of the Puppeteer: "The hand of the Almighty saved the fatherland." And when N. Polevoy himself wrote patriotic plays: “Grandfather of the Russian Fleet” and “Merchant Igolkin,” then, as his brother says, the sovereign was delighted with his dramatic talent: “The author has extraordinary talents,” he said, “ he needs to write, write, write! That's what - he needs to write (he smiled), and not publish a magazine" (Notes of Xenophon Polevoy, St. Petersburg, ed. Suvorin, 1888, p. 445.). And do not think that the Russian rulers were any exception in this case. No, such a typical representative of absolutism, as Louis XIV was in France, was no less firmly convinced that art cannot serve as an end in itself, but must contribute to the moral education of people. And all the literature, all the art of the famous century of Louis XIV was thoroughly imbued with this conviction. Likewise, Napoleon I would have looked at the theory of art for art’s sake as one of the harmful inventions of unpleasant “ideologists.” He also wanted literature and art to serve moral purposes. And he succeeded to a large extent, since, for example, most of the paintings exhibited at periodic exhibitions of that time ("Salons") were devoted to depicting the military exploits of the imperial consulate. His little nephew Napoleon III followed in his footsteps on this occasion, although with much less success. He also wanted to make art and literature serve what he called morality. In November 1852, the Lyon professor Laprade caustically ridiculed this Bonapartist desire for edifying art in a satire entitled "Les muses d" Etat." He predicted there that the time would soon come when the state muses would subordinate the human mind to military discipline, and then the reign of order, then no writer will dare to express any dissatisfaction. Il faut être content, s"il pleut, s"il fait soleil, S"il fait chaud, s"il fait froid: "Ayez le teint vermeil, Je déteste les gens maigres, à face pâle; Celui qui ne rit pas mérite qu"on l"empale", etc. I will note in passing that for this witty satire Laprade lost his professorship. The government of Napoleon III did not tolerate ridicule of the "state muses".

II

But let's leave government "spheres". Among the French writers of the second empire there are people who rejected the theory of art for art's sake not for any progressive reasons. Thus, Alexandre Dumas the son categorically stated that the words “art for art’s sake” have no meaning. With his plays "Le fils naturel" and "Le père prodigue" he pursued well-known social goals. He found it necessary to support with his writings the “old society,” which, according to him, was collapsing on all sides. In 1857, Lamartine, summing up the literary activity of the then recently deceased Alfred Musset, regretted that it did not serve as an expression of religious, social, political or patriotic beliefs (foi), and reproached the poets of his time for forgetting the meaning of their works for the sake of rhyme or meter. Finally, to point out a much less significant literary value, Maxime Ducamp (Ducamp), condemning the exclusive predilection for form, exclaims: La forme est belle, soit! quand l"idée est au fond! Qu"est ce donc qu"un beau front, qui n"a pas de cervelle? He also attacks the head of the romantic school in painting for the fact that, “like some writers who created art for art’s sake, M. Delacroix invented paint for paint. History and humanity serve for him only as a reason for combining well-chosen shades.” According to the same writer, the school of art for art’s sake has forever outlived its time (For this see the excellent book by A. Cassagne, La théorie de l'art pour l'art en France chez les derniers romantiques et les premiers réalistes, Paris 1906, p. p. 96--105.). Lamartine and Maxime Dukan can just as little be suspected of any destructive aspirations as Alexandre Dumas the son. They rejected the theory of art not because they wanted to replace the bourgeois order with some new social system, but because they wanted to strengthen bourgeois relations, which had been significantly shaken by the liberation movement of the proletariat. In this regard, they differed from the romantics, and especially from the Parnassians and the first realists, only in that they were incomparably better at putting up with the bourgeois way of life. Some were conservative optimists where others were equally conservative pessimists. From all this it follows with complete conviction that the utilitarian view of art gets along just as well with a conservative mood as with a revolutionary one. The inclination to such a view necessarily presupposes only one condition: a living and active interest in a known, no matter which one, social order or social ideal, and it disappears wherever this interest disappears for one reason or another. Now let us go further and see which of the two opposing views of art is more favorable to its success. Like all questions of social life and social thought, this question does not admit of an unconditional solution. It all depends on the conditions of time and place. Let us remember Nicholas I and his servants. They wanted to make of Pushkin, Ostrovsky and other contemporary artists servants of morality, as the gendarme corps understood it. Let us assume for a moment that they managed to carry out this firm intention. What was supposed to come out of this? It's not difficult to answer. The muses of artists who submitted to their influence would, having become state muses, show the most obvious signs of decline and would lose extremely much in their truthfulness, strength and attractiveness. Pushkin's poem "To the Slanderers of Russia" cannot at all be classified as one of his best poetic creations. Ostrovsky’s play “Don’t Get in Your Own Sleigh,” favorably recognized as a “useful lesson,” is also God knows how successful. Meanwhile, Ostrovsky took only a few steps in the direction towards the ideal that the Benckendorffs, Shirinsky-Shikhmatovs and others like them, supporters of useful art, sought to realize. Let us further assume that Théophile Gautier, Théodore de Banville Lecomte de Lisle, Baudelaire, the Goncourt brothers, Flaubert - in short, all the romantics, the Parnassians and the first French realists - reconciled themselves with the bourgeois environment that surrounded them and gave their muses in the service of those to the gentlemen who, as Banville expressed it, valued first and foremost the five-franc piece. What would come of this? Again, it’s not difficult to answer. The Romantics, the Parnassians and the first French realists would have sunk very low. Their works would be much less powerful, much less truthful and much less attractive. Which is higher in artistic merit: Flaubert's "Madame Bovary" or Ogier's "Le gendre de monsieur Poirier"? It seems there is no need to ask about this. And the difference here is not only in talent. Ogier's dramatic vulgarity, which represents a real apotheosis of bourgeois moderation and accuracy, inevitably presupposed completely different methods of creativity than those used by Flaubert, Goncourt and other realists, who contemptuously turned away from this moderation and accuracy. Finally, there was also a reason for the fact that one literary movement attracted much more talent than the other. What does this prove? Something that romantics like Théophile Gautier never agreed with, namely, that the dignity of a work of art is ultimately determined by the specific gravity of its content. T. Gautier said that poetry not only does not prove anything, but does not even tell anything, and that the beauty of a poem is determined by its music, its rhythm. But this is a huge mistake. Quite the opposite: poetic and artistic works in general always tell something, because they always express something. Of course, they “tell” in their own special way. An artist expresses his idea with images, while a publicist proves his idea with the help of logical conclusions. And if a writer uses logical arguments instead of images, or if he comes up with images to prove a well-known theme, then he is not an artist, but a publicist, even if he wrote not studies and articles, but novels, stories or theatrical plays. All this is true. But from all this it does not at all follow that in a work of art the idea does not matter. I will say more: there cannot be a work of art devoid of ideological content. Even those works whose authors value only the form and do not care about the content still express a certain idea in one way or another. Gautier, who did not care about the ideological content of his poetic works, assured, as we know, that he was ready to sacrifice his political rights as a French citizen for the pleasure of seeing a genuine painting by Raphael or a naked beauty. One was closely connected with the other: exclusive concern for form was determined by socio-political indifference. Works whose authors value only form always express the well-known - as I explained earlier, hopelessly negative - attitude of their authors towards the social environment around them. And this is the idea common to all of them together and expressed in different ways by each of them individually. But if there is no work of art that is completely devoid of ideological content, then not every idea can be expressed in a work of art. Ruskin says it well: a girl can sing about lost love, but a miser cannot sing about lost money. And he rightly notes that the dignity of a work of art is determined by the height of the mood it expresses. “Ask yourself about any feeling that has taken a strong hold of you,” he says, “can it be sung by a poet, can it inspire him in a positive, true sense? If yes, then the feeling is good. If it cannot be sung, or can only inspire in the direction of the funny, then this is a low feeling." It cannot be otherwise. Art is one of the means of spiritual communication between people. And the higher the feeling expressed by a given work of art, the more With great convenience, other things being equal, this work can play its role as the indicated means. Why can’t a miser sing about lost money? Very simply: because if he were to sing about his loss, then his song would not touch anyone, i.e. . could not serve as a means of communication between him and other people. They can point to war songs and ask me: does war serve as a means of communication between people? I will answer this that war poetry, while expressing hatred of the enemy, at the same time glorifies the selflessness of warriors - their willingness to die for their homeland, for their state, etc. It is to the extent that it expresses such readiness that it serves as a means of communication between people within those boundaries (tribe, community, state) , the breadth of which is determined by the level of cultural development achieved by humanity, or rather, by a given part of it. I. S. Turgenev, who strongly disliked preachers of the utilitarian view of art, once said: Venus de Milo is undoubtedly more in line with the principles of 1789. He was absolutely right. But what follows from this? This is not at all what I. S. Turgenev wanted to prove. There are a lot of people in the world who not only “doubt” the principles of 1789, but have absolutely no idea about them. Ask a Hottentot who has not gone through the European school what he thinks of these principles. You will be convinced that he has never heard of them. But the Hottentot knows nothing not only of the principles of 1789, but also of the Venus de Milo. And if he sees her, he will certainly “doubt” her. He has his own ideal of beauty, images of which are often found in anthropological works under the name of the Hottentot Venus. The Venus de Milo is "undoubtedly" attractive only to a certain portion of the white race. For this part of this race it is indeed more certain than the principles of 1789. But for what reason? Only because these principles express relations that correspond only to a certain phase in the development of the white race - the time of the establishment of the bourgeois order in its struggle with the feudal (Second article of the “Proclamation of the Rights of Man and the Citizen”, adopted by the French Constituent Assembly in the sessions of the 20th -August 26, 1789 , reads: “Le but de toute association politique est la conservation des droits naturels et imprescriptibles de l”homme. Ces droits sont: la liberté, la propriété, la sûreté et la résistance à l "oppression". Concern for property testifies to the bourgeois nature of the revolution that was taking place, and the recognition of the right to resist oppression shows that the revolution was just being carried out, but was not completed, encountering strong resistance from the secular and spiritual aristocracy. In June 1848, the French bourgeoisie no longer recognized the right of a citizen to resist oppression.), - and the Venus de Milo is an ideal of female appearance that corresponds to many phases of the same development. Many, but not all. Christians had their own ideal of female appearance. It can be found on Byzantine icons. Everyone knows that fans of such icons very much “doubted” the Milos and all other Venuses. They called them devils and destroyed them wherever they had them. there's an opportunity. Then a time came when the ancient devils again began to appeal to people of the white race. This time was prepared by the liberation movement among Western European townspeople, that is, precisely the movement that was most clearly expressed precisely in the principles of 1789. Therefore, contrary to Turgenev, we can say that the Venus de Milo became the more “undoubted” in the new Europe, the more mature the European population was to proclaim the principles of 1789. This is not a paradox, but a naked historical fact. The whole point of the history of art in the Renaissance - considered from the point of view of the concept of beauty - is that the Christian-monastic ideal of human appearance is gradually pushed into the background by that earthly ideal, the emergence of which was determined by the liberation movement of cities, and the development of which was facilitated by the memory about ancient devils. Even Belinsky, who quite rightly asserted in the last period of his literary activity that “pure,” detached, unconditional, or, as philosophers say, “absolute art has never happened anywhere,” admitted, however, that “the works of painting of the Italian school of the 16th century , to a certain extent, approached the ideal of absolute art, since they were the creation of an era during which “art was the main interest, exclusively occupying the educated part of society." For example, he pointed to “Raphael’s Madonna, this chef-d’oeuvre of Italian painting XVI century", i.e. the so-called Sistine Madonna, located in the Dresden Gallery. But the Italian schools of the 16th century completed a long process of struggle between the earthly ideal and the Christian monastic ideal. And no matter how exceptional the interest of the most educated part of society of the 16th century in art was, (its exclusivity, which cannot be denied, only means that in the 16th century there was a hopeless discord between people who valued art and the social environment that surrounded them. This discord even then gave rise to a gravitation towards pure art, that is, art for art's sake. In earlier times, say - during Giotto, there was neither the indicated discord nor the indicated gravity.) it is undeniable that Raphael's Madonnas are one of the most characteristic artistic expressions of victory earthly ideal over the Christian-monastic one. This can be said without any exaggeration even about those of them that were written at a time when Raphael was under the influence of his teacher Perugino, and whose faces apparently reflect a purely religious mood. Through their religious appearance one can see such great strength and such a healthy joy of a purely earthly life that they no longer have anything in common with the pious virgins of the Byzantine masters (It is remarkable that Perugino himself was suspected of atheism by his contemporaries. Sovremennik, book XII, 1912 The works of the Italian masters of the 16th century were just as little creations of “absolute art” as the works of all previous masters, starting with Cimabue and Duccio di Buoninsegna. Such art, in fact, has never existed anywhere. And if I. S. Turgenev referred to the Venus de Milo as a product of such art, then this happened solely because he, like all idealists, mistakenly looked at the actual course of aesthetic development of mankind.The ideal of beauty dominant at a given time, in a given society or in a given class of society, is rooted partly in the biological conditions of the development of the human race, which create, among other things, racial characteristics, and partly in the historical conditions of the emergence and existence of this society or this class. And that is precisely why it is always very rich in quite definite and not at all absolute, that is, not unconditional content. Whoever worships “pure beauty” does not at all make himself independent of those biological and socio-historical conditions that determined his aesthetic taste, but only more or less consciously closes his eyes to these conditions. This was the case, by the way, with romantics like Théophile Gautier. I have already said that his exceptional interest in the form of poetic works was in close causal connection with his socio-political indifference. This indifferentism elevated the dignity of his poetic creations insofar as it protected him from being carried away by bourgeois vulgarity, moderation and accuracy. But he lowered this dignity, since he limited Gautier’s horizons and prevented him from assimilating the advanced ideas of his time. Let's take the already familiar preface to "Mademoiselle de Maupin", which contains such almost childishly perky antics against the defenders of the utilitarian view of art. Gautier exclaims in it: “God! How stupid is this imaginary ability of the human race for self-improvement, with which all our ears have been buzzing! One might think that the human machine is capable of improving, and that by correcting some wheel in it or better arranging its parts, we let us make her carry out her duties with greater ease" (Mademoiselle de Maupin, Préface, p. 23.). To prove that this is not so, Gautier refers to Marshal Bassompierre, who drained a whole boot of wine for the health of his guns. He notes that it would be as difficult for this marshal to improve in terms of drinking as it would be for a modern person to surpass Milo of Croton, who ate a whole bull in one sitting, in terms of food. These remarks, which in themselves are completely fair, could not be more characteristic of the theory of art for art’s sake in the form in which it received from the consistent romantics. The question arises: who buzzed Gautier’s ears with talk about the ability of the human race to self-improvement? Socialists, and specifically Saint-Simonists, who had great success in France not long before the time when the novel “Mademoiselle de Maupin” appeared. It is against the Saint-Simonists that he directs his thoughts, which are absolutely correct in themselves, about the difficulty of surpassing Marshal Bassompierre in drunkenness and Milo of Croton in gluttony. But these in themselves correct considerations become completely inappropriate when directed against Saint-Simonists. The self-improvement of the human race that the Saint-Simonists spoke about has nothing to do with increasing the volume of the stomach. The Saint-Simonists had in mind the improvement of social organization in the interests of the largest part of the population, that is, its working productive part. To call such a task stupid and to ask whether its solution would lead to an increase in the human ability to get drunk on wine and gorge on meat was to reveal precisely that bourgeois narrow-mindedness that spoiled so much blood for young romantics. How did this happen? How did bourgeois narrow-mindedness creep into the reasoning of that very writer who saw the whole meaning of his existence in the life and death struggle with it? I have already answered this question more than once, albeit in passing, and, as the Germans say, in another connection, by comparing the mood of the romantics with the mood of David and his friends. I said that while rebelling against bourgeois tastes and habits, the romantics had nothing against the bourgeois social order. Now we need to look at this more carefully. Some romantics, for example, Georges Sand - during the years of his rapprochement with Pierre Leroux - sympathized with socialism. But these were exceptions. The general rule was that, while rebelling against bourgeois vulgarity, the romantics were at the same time very unfriendly to socialist systems that pointed to the need for social reform. The Romantics wanted to change social mores without changing anything in the social structure. It goes without saying that this is completely impossible. Therefore, the revolt of the romantics against the “bourgeois” led to as few practical consequences as the contempt of the Göttingen or Jena Fuchs for the philistines. The romantic revolt against the “bourgeois” was completely fruitless in practical terms. But its practical futility had important literary consequences. She conveyed to the romantic heroes that character of stiltedness and fictionality, which ultimately led to the collapse of the school. The stilted and fictitious character of the heroes cannot in any way be recognized as an advantage of a work of art, therefore, next to the above-mentioned plus we should now put a well-known minus: if romantic works of art benefited a lot thanks to the rebellion of their authors against the “bourgeois”, then, on the other hand, they did not They lost little due to the practical futility of this uprising. Already the first French realists made every effort to eliminate the main drawback of romantic works: their fictitious, stilted nature heroes. In Flaubert's novels there is not a trace of romantic fiction and stiltedness (except, perhaps, "Salambo" and even "Les contes"). The first realists continue to rebel against the “bourgeois,” but they rebel against them in a different way. They do not contrast unprecedented heroes with bourgeois vulgarities, but try to make vulgarities the subject of an artistically faithful depiction. Flaubert considered it his duty to treat the social environment he depicted as objectively as a natural scientist treats nature. “We must treat people like mastodons or crocodiles,” he says. “Can you get excited about the horns of some and the jaws of others? Show them, make stuffed animals out of them, put them in jars of alcohol, "That's all. But don't pronounce moral judgments about them; and who are you, you little toads?" And since Flaubert managed to remain objective, the persons he depicted in his works acquired the significance of such “documents,” the study of which is absolutely necessary for anyone involved in the scientific study of socio-psychological phenomena. Objectivity was the strongest side of his method, but, while remaining objective in the process of artistic creation, Flaubert never ceased to be very subjective in assessing the social movements of his time. In him, like in Théophile Gautier, cruel contempt for the “bourgeois” was complemented by strong hostility towards all those who in one way or another encroached on bourgeois social relations. And his hostility was even stronger. He was a strong opponent of universal suffrage, which he called "a shame on the human mind." “With universal suffrage,” he wrote Georges Sand, “number rules over the mind, over education, over race, and even over money, which is worth more than number (argent... vaut mieux que le nombre).” In another letter he says that universal suffrage is more stupid than the right of God. Socialist society seemed to him “a huge monster that will absorb every individual action, every personality, every thought, will direct everything and do everything.” We see from this that in his negative attitude towards democracy and socialism, this hater of the “bourgeois” was in complete agreement with the most limited ideologists of the bourgeoisie. And the same trait is noticeable in all contemporary supporters of art for art’s sake. In an essay on the life of Edgar Poe, Baudelaire, who had long forgotten his revolutionary “Salut public,” says: “In a people deprived of an aristocracy, the cult of beauty can only deteriorate, diminish and disappear.” Elsewhere he states that there are only three honorable beings: "priest, warrior, poet." This is no longer conservatism, but a reactionary mood. Barbey d'Orvelly is the same reactionary. In his book "Les poètes", he, speaking about the poetic works of Laurent Pich, admits that he could have been a great poet "if he had wanted to trample underfoot atheism and democracy - these two disgraces (ces deux déshonneurs) of his thought." (Les poètes, MDCCCXXCIII, p. 260.) Much water has passed under the bridge since Théophile Gautier wrote (in May 1835) his preface to Mademoiselle de Maupin. The Simonists, who seemed to have buzzed his ears with talk about the capacity of the human race for self-improvement, loudly proclaimed the need for social reform. But, like most utopian socialists, they were resolute supporters of peaceful social development, and therefore no less resolute opponents of class struggle. Moreover, utopian socialists addressed mainly to the propertied people. They did not believe in the independent activity of the proletariat. But the events of 1848 showed that its independent activity could become very formidable. After 1848, the question was no longer whether the haves would want to take up the task of improving the lot of the have-nots, but in who will prevail in the mutual struggle: the haves or the have-nots. Interclass relations between classes in modern society have been greatly simplified. Now all the ideologists of the bourgeoisie understood that the question was whether they would be able to keep the working masses in economic enslavement. This awareness also penetrated the minds of supporters of art for the propertied. One of the most remarkable among them in terms of its importance in science, Ernest Renan, in his essay “La réforme intellectuelle et morale” demanded a strong government, “which would force the good hillbilly to do part of the work for us while we indulge in reflection” (“qui force de bons rustiques de faire notre part de travail pendant que noua spéculons") (Quoted from Cassagne in his book "La théorie de l"art pour l"art chez les derniers rornantiquers et les premiers réalistes", p. 194--195 .). This incomparably clearer understanding than before by bourgeois ideologists of the meaning of the struggle between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat could not but have a strong influence on the nature of the “reflections” to which they indulged. Ecclesiastes says excellently: “By oppressing others, the wise become foolish.” The discovery by bourgeois ideologists of the secret of the struggle between their class and the proletariat led to the fact that they gradually lost the ability to calmly scientifically study social phenomena. And this greatly reduced the intrinsic value of their more or less scientific works. If previously bourgeois political economy could put forward such a giant of scientific thought as David Ricardo, now talkative dwarfs like Frederic Bastiat began to set the tone among its representatives. In philosophy, more and more And The idealistic reaction began to strengthen more and more, the essence of which lies in the conservative desire to reconcile the successes of modern natural science with the old religious tradition, or, to put it more precisely, to reconcile the chapel with the laboratory (“On peut, sans contradiction, aller successivement à son laboratoire et à son oratoire” ( “You can, without contradicting yourself, move successively from the laboratory to the chapel,” said Grasset, professor of clinical medicine at Montpellier, ten years ago. This saying of his is enthusiastically repeated by theorists like Jules Suri, author of the book “Bréviaire de l”histoire du matérialisme", written in the spirit of Lange's famous work on the same topic. (See the article "Oratoire et laboratoire" in Suri's collection "Campagnes nationalistes", Paris 1902, 233--266, 267). See in the same collection . article "Science et Religion", the main idea of ​​which is expressed in the famous words of Dubois-Raymond - ignoramus et ignorabimus.) Art did not escape the common fate. We will see to what ridiculous absurdities the influence of the current idealistic reaction has driven some of the newest painters. Now for now I will say the following. The conservative and partly even reactionary way of thinking of the first realists did not prevent them from thoroughly studying their environment and creating things that were very valuable artistically. But there is no doubt that he greatly narrowed their field of vision. By turning hostilely away from the great liberation movement of their time, they thereby excluded from the number of “mastodons” and “crocodiles” they observed the most interesting specimens, those with the richest inner life. Their objective attitude towards the environment they studied meant a lack of sympathy for it. And, of course, they could not sympathize with the fact that, with their conservatism, only one thing was accessible to their observation: “petty thoughts” and “petty passions” born in the “unclean mud” of everyday bourgeois existence. But this lack of sympathy for objects observed and invented quite soon caused and was bound to cause a decline in interest in him. Naturalism, to which they laid the first foundation with their remarkable works, soon found itself, as Huysmans put it, in “a stupid alley, a tunnel with a blocked exit.” He could, as Huysmans put it, make his subject everything up to and including syphilis (In saying this, Huysmans was hinting at the Belgian Tabaran's novel Les virus d'amour.). But the modern labor movement remained inaccessible to him. I remember, of course, that Zola wrote " Germinai". But, leaving aside the weaknesses of this novel, we must not forget that if Zola himself began, as he said, to lean towards socialism, then his so-called experimental method to the end remained little suitable for the artistic study and depiction of great social movements. This method was closely associated with the point of view of that materialism, which Marx called natural science and which does not understand that the actions, inclinations, tastes and habits of thought of a social person cannot find a sufficient explanation for themselves in physiology or pathology, since they are determined by social relations. By staying true to this method, artists could study and depict their "mastodons" and "crocodiles" as individuals rather than as members of a great whole. This is what Huysmans felt, saying that naturalism had found itself in a blind alley and that he had no choice but to talk once again about the love affair of the first wine merchant he met with the first petty shopkeeper he met (See Jules Huret, Enquête sur l'évolution littéraire, conversation with Huysmans, pp. 176--177). Narratives of such relations could be of interest only if they shed light on a certain side of social relations, as was the case in Russian realism. But public interest was absent among the French realists. As a result of this the depiction of "the love affair of the first wine merchant he met with the first petty shopkeeper he met" eventually became uninteresting, boring and even simply disgusting. In his first works, for example, in the novel "Les soeurs Vatard", Huysmans himself was a pure naturalist. But he was tired of the image “the seven deadly sins” (his words again), and he abandoned naturalism, according to the German expression, throwing out the baby with the bath water. In the strange, in places extremely boring, but extremely instructive novel with its very shortcomings "A rebours", he, in the person of Desessent, depicted, or it would be better to say in the old way: he composed, a kind of superman (from completely degenerate aristocrats), the whole complex whose life was supposed to represent a complete negation of the life of the “wine merchant” and the “petty shopkeeper.” The writing of such types once again confirmed the validity of Leconte de Lille’s thought that where there is no real life, the task of poetry is to create an ideal life. But Desessent's ideal life is so devoid of any human content that her writing did not offer the slightest way out of the stupid alley. And so Huysmans fell into mysticism, which served as an “ideal” way out of a situation from which it was impossible to get out through the “real” way. Under the circumstances, this could not have been more natural. However, let's see what we come up with. An artist who has become a mystic does not neglect the ideological content, but only gives it a unique character. Mysticism is also an idea, but only dark, formless, like fog, in mortal enmity with reason. The mystic is not averse to not only telling, but even proving. Only he tells something “not done”, and in his evidence he takes the denial of common sense as the starting point. The example of Huysmans again shows that a work of art cannot do without ideological content. But when artists become blind to the most important social trends of their time, then the nature of the ideas they express in their works greatly decreases in their intrinsic value. And these latter inevitably suffer from this. This circumstance is so important for the history of art and literature that we will have to carefully consider it from various angles. But before we take on this task, let’s tally up the conclusions to which the previous study led us. The tendency towards art for art's sake appears and is strengthened where there is a hopeless discord between people involved in art and the social environment around them. This discord has a beneficial effect on artistic creativity to the very extent that it helps artists rise above their environment. This was the case with Pushkin in the Nicholas era. This was the case with the Romantics, the Parnassians and the first realists in France. By multiplying the number of examples, it would be possible to prove that this has always been the case where the indicated discord existed. But, rebelling against the vulgar mores of the social environment around them, the romantics, Parnassians and realists had nothing against the social relations in which these vulgar mores were rooted. On the contrary, while cursing the “bourgeois,” they valued the bourgeois system—at first instinctively, and then with full consciousness. And the more the liberation movement directed against the bourgeois system intensified in modern Europe, the more conscious the attachment to this system of the French supporters of art for art's sake became. And the more conscious their attachment became, the less they could remain indifferent to the ideological content of their works. But their blindness to the new trend, aimed at renewing all social life, made their views erroneous, narrow, one-sided and lowered the quality of the ideas that were expressed in their works. The natural result of this was the hopeless situation of French realism, which gave rise to decadent hobbies and a tendency towards mysticism in writers who themselves had once gone through the realistic (naturalistic) school. This conclusion will be tested in detail in the next article. Now it's time to finish. In conclusion, I will only say two more words about Pushkin. When his poet trashes the “rabble,” we hear a lot of anger in his words, but we don’t hear vulgarity, no matter what D.I. Pisarev says. The poet reproaches the secular crowd, namely the secular crowd, and not the real people, who stood completely outside the field of view of Russian literature of that time, for the fact that the stove pot is more valuable to them than the Apollo Belvedere. This means that her narrow practicality is intolerable to him. But only. His decisive reluctance to teach the crowd only testifies to his completely hopeless view of it. But there is no reactionary taste to it. And this is Pushkin’s huge advantage over such defenders of art for art’s sake as Gautier was. This advantage is conditional. Pushkin did not mock the Saint-Simonists. But he had hardly even heard of them. He was an honest and generous man. But this honest and generous man had internalized well-known class prejudices since childhood. Eliminating the exploitation of one class by another must have seemed to him an unrealistic and even ridiculous utopia. If he had heard about any practical plans for its elimination, and especially if these plans had caused such a stir in Russia as the Saint-Simonist plans in France, then he would probably have taken up arms against them in sharp polemical articles and mocking epigrams . Some of his remarks - in the article "Thoughts on the Road" - about the advantages of the position of the Russian serf peasant in comparison with the position of the Western European worker make us think that in this case the intelligent Pushkin could sometimes reason almost as unsuccessfully as the incomparably less intelligent reasoned Gautier. Russia's economic backwardness saved him from this possible weakness. This is an old but ever new story. When a given class lives by exploiting another class below it on the economic ladder, and when it has achieved complete dominance in society, then moving forward means for this class to go down. This is the solution to the seemingly incomprehensible and even, perhaps, incredible phenomenon that in economically backward countries, the ideology of the ruling classes often turns out to be much higher than in advanced ones. Now Russia has already reached that height of economic development at which supporters of the theory of art for art's sake become conscious defenders of a social order based on the exploitation of one class by another. That’s why we now say a lot of socially reactionary nonsense in the name of “absolute autonomy of art.” But in Pushkin’s time it was not like that. And this was great happiness for him. I said that there is no work of art that is completely devoid of ideological content. To this I added that not every idea can form the basis of a work of art. Only that which promotes communication between people can give true inspiration to an artist. The possible limits of such communication are determined not by the artist, but by the height of culture achieved by the social whole to which he belongs. But in a society divided into classes, the matter also depends on the mutual relations of these classes and on what phase of its development each of them is at a given time. When the bourgeoisie was just trying to achieve its liberation from the yoke of the secular and spiritual aristocracy, that is, when it itself was a revolutionary class, then it led the entire working masses, which together with it constituted one “third” estate. And then the leading ideologists of the bourgeoisie were also the leading ideologists of “the entire nation, with the exception of the privileged.” In other words, at that time the limits of communication between people, the means of which were the works of artists who stood on the bourgeois point of view, were relatively very wide. But when the interests of the bourgeoisie ceased to be the interests of the entire working masses, and especially when they came into hostile conflict with the interests of the proletariat, then the limits of this communication became very narrow. If Ruskin said that a miser cannot sing about the money he has lost, now the time has come when the mood of the bourgeoisie began to approach the mood of the miser mourning his treasures. The only difference is that this miser mourns a loss that has already occurred, and the bourgeoisie loses peace of mind from the loss that threatens it in the future. “By oppressing others,” I said in the words of Ecclesiastes, “the wise become foolish.” The same harmful effect must have on the wise (even the wise!) the fear that he will lose the opportunity to oppress others. The ideologies of the ruling class lose their intrinsic value as it becomes ripe for destruction. The art created by his experiences falls. The purpose of this article is to supplement what was said on this subject in the previous article, by considering some more of the most striking signs of the current decline of bourgeois art. We have seen how mysticism penetrated into modern fiction France. What led to him was the consciousness of the impossibility of limiting oneself to form without content, that is, without an idea, accompanied by the inability to rise to the understanding of the great liberating ideas of our time. The same consciousness and the same inability led to many other consequences, no less than mysticism, reducing the internal value of works of art. Mysticism is irreconcilably hostile to reason. But it is not only those who embrace mysticism who are at enmity with reason. He is also at enmity with those who, for one reason or another, in one way or another defend a false idea. And when a false idea is placed at the basis of a work of art, it introduces such internal contradictions into it that its aesthetic dignity inevitably suffers. As an example of a work of art that suffers from the falsity of its main idea, I have already had to point to Knut Hamsun’s play “At the Royal Gates” (See my article “The Son of Doctor Stockman” in my collection “From Defense to Attack.”). The reader will forgive me if I remind him of it again. The hero of this play appears before us as a young and, if perhaps not talented, then at least extremely arrogant writer Ivar Careno. He calls himself a man “with free thoughts like a bird.” What does this thinker, free as a bird, write about? About "resistance". About "hatred". Who does he advise to resist? Whom does he teach to hate? He advises resistance to the proletariat. He teaches us to hate the proletariat. Isn't it true that this is one of the newest heroes? We have so far seen very few of these, not to say we have not seen them at all, in fiction. But the man who preaches resistance to the proletariat is the most undoubted ideologist of the bourgeoisie. That ideologist of the bourgeoisie, who is called Ivar Careno, seems to himself and his creator Knut Hamsun the greatest revolutionary. We learned from the example of the first French romantics that there are such “revolutionary” sentiments, the main distinguishing feature of which is their conservatism. Théophile Gautier hated the “bourgeois” and at the same time thundered against people who said that it was time to eliminate bourgeois social relations. Ivar Careno is obviously one of the spiritual descendants of the famous French romantic. However, the descendant went much further than his ancestor. He is consciously at enmity with that for which the ancestor had only instinctive hostility (I am talking about the time when Gaultier had not yet worn out his famous red vest. Subsequently - for example, during the Paris Commune - he was already conscious - and how ardent! - the enemy of the liberation aspirations of the working class. It should be noted, however, that Flaubert can also be called the ideological predecessor of Knut Hamsun, and even, perhaps, with even greater right. In one of his notebooks the following remarkable lines are found: “Ce n”est pas contre Dieu que Prométhée aujourd”hui devrait se révolter, mais contre le Peuple, dieu nouveau. Aux vieilles tyrannies sacerdotales, féodales et monarchiques on a succédé une autre, plus subtile, inextricable, impérieuse et qui dans quelque temps ne laissera pas un seul coin de la (erre qui soit libre." ("At present, Prometheus would no longer have to rebel against God, but against the people, this new god. Old The tyranny of the clergy, feudal lords and monarchy was replaced by a new, more subtle, complex, imperious one, which after a while will not leave a single free corner on earth"). See the chapter Les carnets de Gustave Flaubert in the book by Louis Bertrand "Gustave Flaubert", Paris, MCMXII, page 255. This is precisely the thought, free as a bird, that inspires Ivar Careno. In a letter to Georges Sand dated September 8, 1871, Flaubert said: “je crois que la foule, le troupeau sera toujours haïssable . Il n"y a d"important qu"un petit groupe d"esprits toujours les mêmes et qui se repassent le flambeau". (“I think that the crowd, the herd, will always be worthy of hatred. What is important is only a small group of always the same minds, passing on the light to one another.”) In the same letter there are the lines I quoted above about universal suffrage, supposedly constituting the shame of the human mind, since thanks to it number dominates “even over money)! (See Flaubert, Correspondance, quatrième série (1869--1880), huitième mille, Paris 1910.) In these views, Ivar Careno would probably recognize their thoughts, free as a bird. But these views have not yet found their direct expression in the novels of Flaubert. The class struggle in modern society had to move far forward before the ideologists of the ruling class felt the need to directly express in literature their hatred of the liberation aspirations of the “people "But those of them who, over time, had this need, could no longer defend the “absolute autonomy” of ideologies. On the contrary, they set ideologies the conscious goal of serving as a spiritual weapon in the fight against the proletariat. But more on that below.). If the romantics were conservatives, then Ivar Careno is a reactionary of the purest water. And, moreover, a utopian like Shchedrinsky wild landowner . He wants to exterminate the proletariat, just as he wanted to exterminate the peasant. This utopia reaches the ultimate limits of comedy. But in general, all of Ivar Careno’s “free, like a bird” thoughts reach the extreme degree of absurdity. The proletariat appears to him as a class that exploits other classes of society. This is the most erroneous of all Kareno’s free-as-a-bird thoughts. And the trouble is that this erroneous thought of his hero is shared, apparently, by Knut Hamsun himself. Ivar Careno suffers all sorts of misadventures with him precisely because he hates the proletariat and “resists” it. Because of this, he loses the opportunity to receive a professorship and even publish his book. In short, he incurs a whole series of persecutions from those bourgeois among whom he lives and acts. But in what part of the world, in what utopia, does the bourgeoisie live, so inexorably taking revenge for the “resistance” to the proletariat? Such a bourgeoisie has never existed anywhere and cannot exist. Knut Hamsun based his play on an idea that is in irreconcilable contradiction with reality. And this damaged the play so much that it causes laughter precisely in those places where, according to the author’s plan, the course of action should have taken a tragic turn. Knut Hamsun is a great talent. But no amount of talent will transform into truth what is its direct opposite. The enormous shortcomings of the drama "At the Royal Gates" are a natural consequence of the complete failure of its main idea. And the inconsistency of her idea is due to the author’s inability to understand the meaning of that mutual struggle of classes in today’s society, the literary echo of which was his drama. Knut Hamsun is not French. But this does not change matters at all. Already the Manifesto of the Communist Party very aptly pointed out that in civilized countries, thanks to the development of capitalism, “national one-sidedness and narrow-mindedness are now becoming more and more impossible, and from many national and local literatures one world literature is being formed.” True, Hamsun was born and raised in one of those countries of Western Europe, which is far from being one of the most developed economically. This, of course, explains the truly childish naivety of his ideas about the position of the struggling proletariat in his contemporary society. But the economic backwardness of his homeland did not prevent him from being imbued with that hostility towards the working class and that sympathy for the struggle against it, which now naturally arises in the bourgeois intelligentsia of the most advanced countries. Ivar Careno is only one of the varieties of the Nietzschean type. What is Nietzscheanism? This is a new edition, revised and expanded, in accordance with the requirements of the newest period of capitalism, of that already well-known struggle against the “bourgeois”, which perfectly coexists with indestructible sympathy for the bourgeois system. Moreover, Hamsun’s example can easily be replaced by another example borrowed from modern French literature. One of the most talented and - what is even more important here - one of the most thoughtful playwrights of modern France, without any doubt, must be recognized as Francois de Curel. And among his dramas, the most worthy of note must be recognized without any hesitation as the five-act play “Le repas du lion,” which, as far as I know, was little noticed by Russian criticism. The main character of this play, Jean de Sancy, at one time, under the influence of some exceptional circumstances of his childhood, is carried away by Christian socialism, and then decisively breaks with it and acts as an eloquent defender of large-scale capitalist production. In the third scene of the fourth act, in a long speech, he proves to the workers that “egoism engaged in production (l"égoisme qui produit) is for the working masses the same as alms for the poor." And since his listeners express their disagreement with this glance, then he, gradually warming up, explains to them in a vivid, picturesque comparison the role of the capitalist and his workers in modern production: “They say,” he booms, “a whole horde of jackals follows a lion into the desert to take advantage of the remains of his prey. Jackals are too weak to attack buffaloes. They are not agile enough to overtake the gazelles, and all their hope lies in the claws of the king of the desert. Do you hear: to his claws! At dusk, he leaves his den and runs, growling with hunger, looking for prey. Here she is! He makes a mighty leap, a fierce struggle begins, a mortal combat occurs, and the ground is covered with blood, which is not always the blood of the victim. Then follows a royal feast, which is watched with attention and reverence by the jackals. When the lion has eaten his fill, the jackals dine. Do you think that these latter would be better fed if the lion divided his spoil equally with each of them, leaving only a small piece for himself? Not at all! This kind lion would cease to be a lion; he would hardly be suitable for the role of a dog leading the blind! He would stop strangling his victim at the first moan and begin to lick her wounds. The lion is good only as a predatory animal, greedy for prey, striving only for murder and bloodshed. When such a lion roars, the jackals salivate." The already clear meaning of this parable is stated by the eloquent speaker in the following much briefer, but equally expressive words: "The entrepreneur opens those nutritious springs that shower the workers with their splashes." I know very well , that the artist is not responsible for the meaning of the speeches pronounced by his heroes. But very often he makes clear his attitude to these speeches in one way or another, as a result of which we get the opportunity to judge his own views. The entire subsequent course of the play “Le repas du lion” shows that de Curel himself considers Jean de Sancy’s comparison of the entrepreneur with a lion, the workers with jackals, to be completely correct. It is clear from everything that he could repeat with complete conviction the words of the same hero: “I believe in the lion. I bow to the rights that his claws give him.” He himself is ready to recognize the workers as jackals, feeding on the crumbs of what the capitalist’s labor produces. The struggle of workers with the entrepreneur seems to him, like Jean de Sancy, as a struggle of envious jackals with a mighty lion. This comparison is the main idea of ​​his play, to which he relates the fate of his main character. But there is not a single atom of truth in this idea. It distorts the actual nature of social relations in modern society much more than the economic sophisms of Bastiat and all his many followers up to Böhm-Bawerk distort them. Jackals do absolutely nothing to obtain what the lion eats and what partially satisfies their own hunger. And who would dare to say that the workers employed in this enterprise do nothing to create its product? After all, despite any economic sophisms, it is clear that it is created precisely by their labor. Of course, the entrepreneur himself participates in the production process as its organizer. And as an organizer he himself belongs to the ranks of the workers. But again, everyone knows that the salary of the plant manager is another matter, and the entrepreneurial profit of the factory owner is another matter. Subtracting the salary from the profit, we get the remainder, which goes to the share of capital as such. The whole question is why capital gets this remainder. And there is not even a hint of a solution to this issue in the eloquent rantings of Jean de Sancy, who, by the way, does not suspect that his own income, as one of the large shareholders of the enterprise, would not be justified even if the completely wrong thing were correct comparing the entrepreneur with ice, and the workers with jackals: he himself did absolutely nothing for the enterprise, limiting himself to receiving a large income from it every year. And if anyone is like a jackal, feeding on what is obtained through the efforts of others, it is precisely the shareholder, whose whole work consists of keeping shares, and even the ideologist of the bourgeois order, who himself does not participate in production, but picks up what remains of the luxurious capital meals. The talented de Curel, unfortunately, himself belongs to the category of such ideologists. In the struggle between wage workers and capitalists, he completely takes the side of these latter, completely incorrectly depicting their actual relationship to those whom they exploit. And what is Bourget’s play “La barricade” if not a call directed by a famous and also undoubtedly talented artist to the bourgeoisie and inviting all members of this class to unite to fight the proletariat? Bourgeois art becomes militant. Its representatives no longer have the right to say about themselves that they were born “not for unrest and not for battle.” No, they are eager for battle and are not at all afraid of the excitement associated with it. But in the name of what are those battles being fought in which they want to take part? Alas, in the name of "self-interest". True, not for personal gain: it would be strange to say that people like de Curel or Bourget act as defenders of capital in the hope of personal enrichment. The “self-interest” for which they experience “excitement” and strive for “battles” is the self-interest of an entire class. But this circumstance does not prevent her from remaining self-interested. And if this is so, then look what we come up with. Why did the romantics of their contemporary “bourgeois” despise them? We already know why: because the “bourgeois” valued, according to Theodore de Banville, the five-franc coin above all else. And what do artists like de Curel, Bourget and Hamsun defend in their works? Those social relations which serve for the bourgeoisie as a source of more five-franc coins. How far these artists are from the romanticism of the good old days! What drove them away from him? Nothing more than the inevitable course of social development. The more the internal contradictions inherent in the capitalist mode of production became aggravated, the more difficult it became for artists who remained faithful to the bourgeois way of thinking to adhere to the theory of art for art's sake - and to live, shutting themselves up, according to the famous French expression, in an ivory tower (tour d'ivoire In the modern civilized world, it seems, there is no country whose bourgeois youth would not sympathize with the ideas of Friedrich Nietzsche. Friedrich Nietzsche despised his “sleepy” (schläfrigen) contemporaries, perhaps even more than Théophile Gautier despised the “bourgeois” of his time . But what were his “sleepy” contemporaries guilty of in Nietzsche’s eyes? What is their main flaw, the source of all the others? The fact is that they do not know how to think, feel, and most importantly, act as befits people who occupy a dominant position in society. Under current historical conditions, this has the meaning of a reproach that they do not show enough energy and consistency in defending the bourgeois order from revolutionary attacks on the part of the proletariat. It is not for nothing that Nietzsche speaks with such anger about socialists. But look again at what we get. If Pushkin and the romantics of his day reproached the “crowd” for valuing the stove pot too much, then the inspirers of today’s neo-romanticists reproach it for being too sluggish in defending it, i.e., for not valuing it enough. Meanwhile, neo-romantics also proclaim, like the romantics of the good old days, the absolute autonomy of art. But is it possible to seriously talk about the autonomy of that art, which is set with the conscious goal of protecting these social relations? Of course not! Such art is undoubtedly utilitarian. If its representatives despise creativity guided by utilitarian considerations, then this is a simple misunderstanding. In fact, for them - not to mention considerations of personal benefit, which can never have a guiding meaning in the eyes of a person truly devoted to art - only considerations that have in mind the benefit of the exploited majority are intolerable. And the benefit of the exploiting minority is the supreme law for them. Thus, the attitude of, say, Knut Hamsun or Francois de Curel to the principle of utilitarianism in art is in fact directly opposite to the attitude of Théophile Gautier or Flaubert, although these latter, as we know, were not at all alien to conservative predilections. But since the time of Gautier and Flaubert, these predilections, thanks to the deepening of social contradictions, have developed so strongly among artists who take a bourgeois point of view that now it is incomparably more difficult for them to consistently adhere to the theory of art for art’s sake. Of course, anyone who imagined that now none of them adheres consistently to this theory would be very mistaken. But, as we will now see, this type of sequence is currently extremely expensive. Neo-romantics, again under the influence of Nietzsche, are very fond of imagining themselves standing “beyond good and evil.” But what does it mean to stand on the other side of good and evil? This means doing such a great historical thing, judgments about which cannot be placed within the framework of given concepts of good and evil that arose on the basis of a given social order. The French revolutionaries of 1793, in the fight against reaction, undoubtedly stood on the other side of good and evil, that is, their activities contradicted those concepts of good and evil that arose on the basis of the old, outdated order. Such a contradiction, which always contains a lot of tragedy, can only be justified by the fact that the activities of revolutionaries, forced to temporarily remain on the other side of good and evil, lead to the fact that evil retreats before good in public life. To take the Bastille, it was necessary to fight its defenders. And whoever wages a struggle of this kind inevitably stands for a time on the other side of good and evil. But since the taking of the Bastille curbed the arbitrariness that could send people to prison “for the sake of its own pleasure” (“parce que tel est notre bon plaisir” - a well-known expression of the French unlimited kings), it forced evil to retreat before good in the public life of France and this justified the temporary stay on the other side of good and evil for people who fought against tyranny. But not for everyone who finds themselves on the other side of good and evil, such an excuse can be found. For example, Ivar Careno probably would not have hesitated at all to leave on the other side of good and evil for the sake of realizing his “free, like a bird, thoughts.” But, as we know, the total sum of these thoughts of his is expressed in the words: an irreconcilable struggle against the liberation movement of the proletariat. Therefore, to cross the other side of good and evil would mean for him to stop being embarrassed in this struggle even by the few rights that the working class managed to achieve in bourgeois society. And if his struggle had been successful, it would have led not to a decrease in evil in public life, but to its increase. Consequently, his temporary departure beyond good and evil would lose all justification, just as he generally loses all justification where he is committed for reactionary purposes. It may be objected to me that, without finding justification for himself from the point of view of the proletariat, Ivar Careno cannot find it from the point of view of the bourgeoisie. I completely agree with this. But the point of view of the bourgeoisie is in this case the point of view of a privileged minority seeking to perpetuate its privileges. And the point of view of the proletariat is the point of view of the majority, which demands the elimination of all privileges. That is why to say that the activity of a given person is justified from the point of view of the bourgeoisie means to admit that it is condemned from the point of view of all people who are not inclined to defend the interests of the exploiters. And this is quite enough for me, since the inevitable course of economic development guarantees me that the number of such people will certainly increase more and more. Hating the “sleepy ones” with all their hearts, neo-romantics want movement. But the movement to which they strive is a protective movement in its opposition to the liberation movement of our time. This is the whole secret of their psychology. And this is the secret of the fact that even the most talented of them cannot create such significant works as they would have created with a different direction of their social sympathies and with a different mindset. We have already seen to what extent the idea that de Curel based his play: “Le repas du lion” is erroneous. A false idea cannot but harm a work of art, since it introduces lies into the psychology of the characters. It would not be difficult to show how much is false in the psychology of the main character of the just named play - Jean de Sancy. But this would force me to make a longer digression than is desirable for the plan of my article. Let me take another example that will allow me to be more concise. The main idea of ​​the play "La barricade" is that in the modern class struggle everyone must participate together with their class. But who does Bourget consider the “most sympathetic figure” in his play? The old worker Gaucheron (These are his own words. See "La barricade". Paris 1910. Préface, p. XIX.) which goes not with the workers, but with the entrepreneur. The behavior of this worker radically contradicts the main idea of ​​the play and can only seem sympathetic to someone who is completely blinded by his sympathy for the bourgeoisie. The feeling that guides Gaucheron is the feeling of a slave looking with respect at his chains. And we have been since the time of gr. Alexei Tolstoy, we know how difficult it is to evoke sympathy for the selflessness of a slave in all those who have not been brought up in the spirit of slavery. Remember Vasily Shibanov, who kept his “slavish fidelity” so amazingly well. He died a hero, despite terrible torture: King, his word is all one: He glorifies his master. Meanwhile, this slavish heroism leaves the modern reader cold, who, in general, is hardly even able to understand how selfless devotion to its owner is possible in a “talking instrument.” But old Gaucheron in Bourget’s play is something like Shibanov, who turned from a serf into a modern proletarian. It takes a lot of dazzle to declare him "the most sympathetic figure" in the play. And in any case, one thing is certain: if Gaucheron is sympathetic, then this shows, contrary to Bourget, that each of us should go not with the class to which he belongs, but with the one whose cause seems more just to him. With his creation, Bourget contradicts his own thought. 11 This is again for the same reason that by oppressing others a wise man becomes foolish. When a talented artist is inspired by a wrong idea, then he spoils his own work. But it is impossible for a modern artist to be inspired by the right idea if he wants to defend the bourgeoisie in its struggle against the proletariat. I said that it is now incomparably more difficult for artists who take a bourgeois point of view than before to consistently adhere to the theory of art for art’s sake. By the way, Bourget also admits this. He expresses himself even more decisively. “The role of an indifferent chronicler,” he says, “is impossible for a mind capable of thinking and for a heart capable of feeling when it comes to these terrible internal wars, on which, as it seems at times, the entire future of the fatherland and civilization depends” ( "La barricade". Préface, p. XXIV.). But here it’s time to make a reservation. A person with a thinking mind and a responsive heart really cannot remain an indifferent spectator of the civil war taking place in modern society. If his field of vision is narrowed by bourgeois prejudices, he will find himself on one side of the “barricade”; if he is not infected by these prejudices, then on the other. This is true. But not all children of the bourgeoisie - and, of course, of any other class - have a thinking mind. Those of them who think do not always have a responsive heart. Thus, it is now easy to remain consistent supporters of the theory of art for art’s sake. It perfectly corresponds to indifference to public - even narrowly class - interests. And the bourgeois social system, perhaps more than any other, can develop such indifference. Where entire generations are brought up in the spirit of the notorious principle: each for himself, and God for all, there it is very natural for egoists to appear, thinking only about themselves and being interested only in themselves. And we actually see that among the modern bourgeoisie there are almost more such egoists than ever before. On this score we have very valuable evidence from one of its most prominent ideologists, namely Maurice Barrès. “Our morality, our religion, our national feeling, all this was collapsing,” he says. “We cannot borrow life rules from them. And while waiting for the time when our teachers will establish reliable truths for us, we have to hold on to the only reality, for our self" (Sous l"oeil des barbares, ed. 1901, p. 18.). When everything "collapsed" for a person except his own "I", then nothing prevents him from playing the role of a calm chronicler of the great war taking place in the depths of modern society. However, no. And then there is something that prevents him from playing this role. This something will be precisely the absence of any public interest, which is so clearly characterized in the lines of Barrès that I quoted. Why would he act as a chronicler? social struggle is a person who is not at all interested in either the struggle or society? Everything related to such a struggle will bring irresistible boredom to him. And if he is an artist, then he will not make even a hint of it in his works. Even there he will be concerned with the “only reality”, that is, with his “I”. And since his “I” may still get bored, having no other company than himself, he will come up with a fantastic, “otherworldly” world for him, standing high above the earth and above all earthly “questions”. This is what many of today's artists do. I'm not slandering them. They themselves admit it. This is what our compatriot Mrs. Z. Gippius writes, for example. "I consider it a natural and essential need human nature- prayer. Every person certainly prays or strives to pray, no matter whether he is aware of it or not, no matter what form his prayer takes and to what God it is addressed. The form depends on the abilities and inclinations of each person. Poetry in general, versification in particular, verbal music is only one of the forms that prayer takes in our soul (Collected poems, preface, p. II.). Of course, this identification of “verbal music” with prayer is completely unfounded. There have been very long periods in the history of poetry during which it had absolutely nothing to do with prayer. But there is no need to argue about this. It was important for me here only to acquaint the reader with the terminology of Mrs. Gippius, since unfamiliarity with this terminology could lead him to some bewilderment when reading the following passages, which are important for us in their essence. Mrs. Gippius continues: “Are we to blame for the fact that each “I” has now become special, lonely, cut off from the other “I”, and therefore incomprehensible to it and unnecessary? We, each of us, passionately need, understand and cherish our prayer, we need our poem , - a reflection of the instant fullness of our heart. But to another, for whom the cherished “mine” is different, my prayer is incomprehensible and alien. The consciousness of loneliness further separates people from each other, isolates, makes the soul withdraw. We are ashamed of our prayers, and , knowing that we won’t merge into them with anyone anyway, we say, we compose them in a low voice, to ourselves, with hints that are clear only to ourselves” (Ibid., p. III.). When individualism reaches such an extreme degree, then, in fact, disappears, as Mrs. Gippius very rightly says, “the possibility of communication precisely in prayer (i.e., in poetry. G. P.), community of prayer (i.e. poetic G. P.) impulse." But poetry and art in general, which serves as one of the means of communication between people, cannot but suffer from this. Even the biblical Jehovah very thoroughly noted that it is not good for a person to be alone. And this is perfectly confirmed by the example of Mrs. Gippius herself. In one from her poems we read: My road is merciless, It leads me to death, But I love myself like God, Love will save my soul. One can doubt this. Who loves “himself as God”? An infinite egoist. And an infinite egoist is unlikely is able to save someone's soul. But the point is not at all whether the souls of Mrs. Gippius and all those who, like her, love “themselves as God” will be saved. The point is that poets who love themselves, as God, they cannot have any interest in what is happening in the society around them. Their aspirations, of necessity, will be to the last degree uncertain. In the poem "Song" Mrs. Gippius "sings": Alas, in insane sadness I die , I'm dying, I strive for what I don't know, I don't know... And this desire I don't know where it comes from, It came from where, But my heart wants and asks for a miracle, A miracle! Oh, let there be something that never happens, Never happens! The pale sky promises me miracles, It promises. But I cry without tears about an incorrect vow, About an incorrect vow... I need something that is not in the world, Which is not in the world. This is perhaps not a bad thing to say. A person who “loves himself like God” and has lost the ability to communicate with other people can only “ask for a miracle” and strive for “what is not in the world”: what is in the world cannot be interesting for him . In Sergeev-Tsensky, Lieutenant Babaev says: “pale infirmity invented art” (Stories, vol. II, p. 128). This philosophizing son of Mars is greatly mistaken in believing that all art is invented by pale infirmity. But it is absolutely undeniable that art, striving for something “that does not exist in the world,” is created by “pale weakness.” It characterizes the decline of an entire system of social relations and is therefore very aptly called decadent. True, the system of social relations whose decline is characterized by this art, that is, the system of capitalist relations of production, is still far from decline in our homeland. In Russia, capitalism has not yet completely overcome the old order. But Russian literature since the time of Peter I has been under the strongest influence of Western European literature. Therefore, it is often penetrated by currents that, while fully consistent with Western European social relations, are much less consistent with the comparatively backward relations in Russia. There was a time when some of our aristocrats were carried away by the teachings of the encyclopedists (It is known, for example, that Helvetius’s work “De l’homme” was published in 1772 in The Hague by one of the Golitsyn princes), which corresponded to one of the last phases of the struggle of the third estate with the aristocracy in France. Now the time has come when many of our "intellectuals" are carried away by social, philosophical and aesthetic teachings corresponding to the era of the decline of the Western European bourgeoisie. This passion anticipates the course of our own social development to the same extent as the enthusiasm of the people of the 18th century did. centuries with the theory of encyclopedists (The fascination of Russian aristocrats with French encyclopedists did not have serious practical consequences at all. However, it was useful in the sense that it still cleared some aristocratic heads of some aristocratic prejudices. On the contrary, the current fascination of some of our intelligentsia philosophical views and aesthetic tastes of the declining bourgeoisie is harmful in the sense that it fills our “intelligent” heads with such bourgeois prejudices for the independent emergence of which the course of social development has not yet sufficiently prepared the Russian soil. These prejudices even penetrate the minds of many Russian people who sympathize with the proletarian movement. Therefore, they form an amazing mixture of socialism and modernism, generated by the decline of the bourgeoisie. This confusion does a lot of harm even in practice.) But if the emergence of Russian decadence cannot be sufficiently explained by our, so to speak, domestic causes, then this does not change its nature at all. Brought to us from the West, it does not cease to be with us what the lady was with herself: the product of the “pale sickness” that accompanies the decline of the class now dominant in Western Europe. Mrs. Gippius will probably say that I completely arbitrarily attributed to her complete indifference to public issues. But, firstly, I did not attribute anything to her, but referred to her own lyrical outpourings, limiting myself to defining their meaning. I leave it to the reader to judge whether I understood these outpourings correctly. Secondly, I know, of course, that Mrs. Gippius is not averse to talking about the social movement now. For example, a book written by her in collaboration with Messrs. D. Merezhkovsky and D. Filosofov and published in Germany in 1908 can serve as convincing evidence in favor of her interest in the Russian social movement. But it is enough to read the preface to this book to see how exclusively the authors strive for what “they do not know.” It says that Europe knows the cause of the Russian revolution, but its soul is unknown. And, probably, in order to acquaint Europe with the soul of the Russian revolution, the authors tell Europeans the following: “We are similar to you, as the left hand is similar to the right... We are equal to you, however, only in the opposite sense... Kant said would be that our spirit lies in the transcendental, and yours in the phenomenal. Nietzsche would say: with you Apollo reigns, with us Dionysus; your genius lies in moderation, ours in impetus. You know how to stop in time; if you come across wall, then you stop or go around it; we hit our heads against it while running (wir rennen uns über die Köpfe ein). It’s not easy for us to swing ourselves, once we’ve swung, we can’t stop. We don’t walk, we run. We don't run, we fly, we don't fly, we fall. You love the golden mean, we love extremes. You are fair, there are no laws for us; You know how to maintain your peace of mind, we always strive to lose it. You possess the kingdom of the present, we seek the kingdom of the future. In the end, you still always put state power above all the freedoms that you can achieve. We remain rebels and anarchists, even when shackled in slave chains. Reason and feeling lead us to the extreme limit of denial, and, despite this, we all, at the deepest basis of our being and will, remain mystics" (Dmitri Mereschkowsky, Zinaida Hippius, Dmitri Philosophoff, Der Zar und die Revolution, München, K. Piper und C-o Verlag, 1908, Seite 1--2.) Next, Europeans learn that the Russian revolution is as absolute as the state form against which it is directed, and that if the empirical conscious goal of this revolution is socialism, then its unconscious mystical the goal is anarchy (Ibid., p. 5). In conclusion, our authors report that they are not addressing the European bourgeoisie, but... do you think, reader, to the proletariat? You are mistaken! “Only to individual minds of universal culture, to people who share Nietzsche’s view that the state is the coldest of all cold monsters,” etc. (Ibid., p. 6.)
I cited these extracts not at all for polemical purposes. I am not conducting polemics here at all, but am only trying to characterize and explain certain sentiments of certain social strata. The extracts I have just made sufficiently show, I hope, that, having become (finally!) interested in social issues, Mrs. Gippius remained the same as she was before us in the poems quoted above: an extreme individualist of a decadent kind, who longs for a “miracle.” precisely because it has no serious relation to living social life. The reader has not forgotten Lecomte de Lille’s thought that poetry now gives an ideal life to those who no longer have a real life. And when a person stops all spiritual communication with the people around him, then his ideal life loses all connection with the earth. And then his fantasy takes him to heaven, then he becomes a mystic. Thoroughly saturated with mysticism, her interest in social issues has absolutely nothing fruitful in itself (G. Merezhkovsky, Gippius and Filosofov in their German book do not at all reject the name “decadents”. They limit themselves to a modest message to Europe that the Russian decadents “have achieved highest peaks world culture." as a science," constitutes a distinctive feature of Russian decadents (Its mystical anarchism, of course, will not frighten absolutely anyone. Anarchism, in general, represents only an extreme conclusion from the basic premises of bourgeois idealism. - That is why we often find sympathy for anarchism among bourgeois ideologists of the period decline. Maurice Barrès also sympathized with anarchism at that time of its development, when he argued that there is no other reality except our “I.” Now he probably has no conscious sympathy for anarchism, since now all the supposedly violent impulses of Barr's individualism. Now those "reliable truths" that he once declared to be "destroyed" have already been "restored" for him. The process of their restoration was accomplished through Barr's transition to the reactionary point of view of the most vulgar nationalism. And there is nothing surprising in such a transition: from extreme bourgeois idealism it’s a stone’s throw to the most reactionary “truths.” Avis for Mrs. Gippius, as well as for Messrs. Merezhkovsky and Filosofov.). The “sober” West, before “drunk” Russia, brought forward people who rebelled against reason in the name of irrational desire. Przybyszewski's Eric Falk scolds social democrats and "salon anarchists like J. Gen. Mackay" for nothing more than their supposedly excessive trust in reason. “All of them,” says this non-Russian decadent, “preach a peaceful revolution, the replacement of a broken wheel with a new one while the cart is in motion. Their whole dramatic structure is idiotically stupid precisely because it is so logical, because it is based on the omnipotence of reason "But until now everything has happened not by reason, but by stupidity, by senseless chance." Falk's reference to “stupidity” and to “senseless accident” is absolutely identical in nature with the desire for “miracle” with which the German book of Mrs. Gippius and Mr. Merezhkovsky and Filosofov is thoroughly imbued. It's the same thought under different names. Its origin is explained by the extreme subjectivism of a significant part of the current bourgeois intelligentsia. When a person considers his own “I” to be the only “reality,” then he cannot admit that there is an objective, “reasonable,” that is, natural, connection between this “I,” on the one hand, and the external world around him, -- with another. The external world must seem to him either completely unreal or only partly real, only to the extent that its existence is based on the only true reality, that is, on our “I”. If such a person loves philosophical speculation, then he will say that, creating the external world, our “I” brings into it at least some share of its rationality; a philosopher cannot completely rebel against reason even when he limits its rights for one reason or another, for example, in the interests of religion (As an example of such a thinker who limited the rights of reason in the interests of religion, one can point to Kant: “Ich mußte also das Wissen aufheben, um zum Glauben Platz zu bekommen". Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Vorrede zur zweiten Ausgabe, S. 26., Leipzig, Druck und Verlag von Philipp Reclam, zweite verbesserte Auflage.) . If a person who considers his own “I” to be the only reality is not inclined to philosophical speculation, then he will not think at all about how the external world is created by this “I”. And then he will not be at all inclined to assume at least some degree of rationality, that is, regularity, in the external world. On the contrary, then this world will appear to him as a kingdom of “meaningless chance.” And if he decides to sympathize with some great social movement, then he will certainly say, like Falk, that its success can be ensured not by the natural course of social development, but only by human “stupidity,” or, which is the same thing, - a “senseless” historical “accident”. But, as I have already said, the mystical view of Gippius and both of her like-minded people on the Russian liberation movement is no different, in essence, from Falk’s view of the “meaningless” causes of great historical events. Trying to amaze Europe with the unheard-of immensity of the freedom-loving aspirations of the Russian people, the authors of the German book I mentioned above remain decadents of the purest water, capable of feeling sympathy only for “what does not happen, never happens,” that is, in other words, unable to treat with sympathy any to what is happening in reality. Therefore, their mystical anarchism does not at all weaken the conclusions that I came to on the basis of the lyrical outpourings of Mrs. Gippius. Once I’ve talked about this, I’ll express my thoughts to the end. The events of 1905-1906 made the same strong impression on Russian decadents as the events of 1848-1849 made on French romantics. They aroused their interest in public life. But this interest was even less suited to the mental make-up of the decadents than it was to the mental make-up of the romantics. Therefore, he turned out to be even less stable. And there is no reason to take it as something serious. Let's return to contemporary art. When a person is disposed to consider his “I” as the only reality, then he, like Mrs. Gippius, “loves himself as God.” This is completely understandable and completely inevitable. And when a person “loves himself as God,” he will begin to concern himself only with himself in his artistic works. The external shooting gallery will interest him only insofar as it somehow concerns the same “sole reality,” the same precious “I.” In Sudermann's very interesting play "Das Blumenboot", Baroness Erffling says to her daughter Thea in the first scene of the second act: "People of our class exist in order to create from the things of this world something like a cheerful panorama that passes before us, or , or rather, it seems to be passing. Because in fact, we are in motion. This is certain. And at the same time, we don’t need any ballast.” These words perfectly indicate the life goal of people of the category to which Ms. Erfflingen belongs, people who with complete conviction can repeat the words of Barrès: “The only reality is ours.” I". But people pursuing such a life goal will look at art only as a means to somehow decorate the panorama that “seems” to pass before them. At the same time, here too they will try not to burden themselves with any ballast. They will either completely neglect the ideological content of works of art or will subject it to the capricious and changeable demands of their extreme subjectivism. Let's turn to painting. Already the impressionists showed complete indifference to the ideological content of their works. One of them said, very successfully expressing the conviction common to all of them: light is the main character in the picture. But the sensation of light is precisely just a sensation, that is, not yet a feeling, not yet a thought. An artist who limits his attention to the area of ​​sensations remains indifferent to feelings and thoughts. He can paint a good landscape. Indeed, the Impressionists painted many superb landscapes. But landscape is not the whole of painting (Among the first impressionists there were many people of great talent. But it is remarkable that among these people of great talent there were no first-rate portrait painters. This is understandable: in portrait painting, light can no longer be the main character. In addition, the landscapes of the outstanding masters of impressionism are good again because they successfully convey the whimsical and varied play of light, and there is little “mood” in them. Feuerbach famously said: “Die Evangelien der Sinne im Zusammenhang lesen heißt denken.” (“To think means coherently read the gospel of feelings"). Without forgetting that by “feelings”, sensuality, Feuerbach understood everything that relates to the field of sensations, we can say that the impressionists did not know how and did not want to read the “gospel of feelings.” This was the main thing defect of their school. It soon led to its degeneration. If the landscapes of the first (in time) and main masters of impressionism are good, then many of the landscapes of their very numerous followers look like caricatures.). Let's remember Leonardo da Vinci's "Last Supper" and ask ourselves: was light the main character in this famous fresco ? It is known that its subject is that moment full of stunning drama in the history of Jesus’ relationship with his disciples when he tells them: “One of you will betray me.” Leonardo da Vinci's task was to depict both the state of mind of Jesus himself, deeply saddened by his terrible discovery, and his disciples, who could not believe that betrayal had crept into their small family. If the artist believed that the main character in the picture is light, then he would not even think of depicting this drama. And if he, nevertheless, painted his fresco, then its main artistic interest would be confined not to what is happening in the soul of Jesus and his disciples, but to what is happening on the walls of the room in which they gathered, on the table , in front of which they sit, and on their own skin, i.e. to a variety of lighting effects. Before us would be not an amazing emotional drama, but a series of well-written spots of light: one, say, on the wall of the room, another on the tablecloth, a third on the hooked nose of Judas, a fourth on the cheek of Jesus, etc. and etc. But, thanks to this, the impression made by the fresco would become incomparably paler, that is, the specific weight of the work of Leonardo da Vinci would be extremely reduced. Some French critics compared impressionism with realism in fiction. And this comparison is not without foundation. But if the impressionists were realists, then their realism should be recognized as completely superficial, not going beyond the “crust of phenomena.” And when this realism won a wide place in modern art - and it undeniably won it - then the painters brought up under its influence were left with one of two things: either to philosophize slyly over the “bark of phenomena”, inventing new, more and more more amazing and more and more artificial light effects, or try to penetrate beyond the “crust of phenomena”, understanding the mistake of the impressionists and realizing that the main character in the picture is not light, but a person with his many different experiences. And we, indeed, see both in modern painting. The focus of interest on the “crust of phenomena” brings to life those paradoxical paintings, in front of which the most indulgent critics throw up their hands in bewilderment, admitting that modern painting is experiencing a “crisis of ugliness” (See Camille Mauclair’s article La crise de la laideur en peinture in his interesting collection entitled: Trois crises de l'art actuel, Paris 1906. ). And the consciousness of the impossibility of limiting oneself to the “bark of phenomena” forces one to seek ideological content, that is, to worship what was burned so recently. However, communicating the ideological content of your works is not as easy as it might seem. An idea is not something that exists independently of the real world. The ideological stock of any given person is determined and enriched by his relationship to this world. And the one whose relationship to this world has developed in such a way that he considers his “I” to be “the only reality” inevitably becomes a complete poor man in terms of ideas. Not only does he not have them, but, most importantly, he has no way of thinking of them. And just as, for lack of bread, people eat quinoa, so, for lack of clear ideas, they are content with vague hints of ideas, surrogates gleaned from mysticism, symbolism and other similar “isms” that characterize eras of decline. In short, what we have already seen in fiction is repeated in painting: realism falls due to its internal emptiness: idealistic reaction triumphs. Subjective idealism has always been based on the idea that there is no other reality other than our “I”. But it took all the boundless individualism of the era of the decline of the bourgeoisie in order to make from this thought not only an egoistic rule defining mutual relations between people, each of whom “loves himself like God” - the bourgeoisie has never been distinguished by an excess of altruism - but also the theoretical basis of the new aesthetics. The reader has, of course, heard about the so-called Cubists. And if he happened to see their products, then I don’t really risk being mistaken in assuming that they didn’t delight him at all. At least for me, these products do not evoke anything resembling aesthetic pleasure. "Nonsense cubed!" - these are the words that come to mind at the sight of these supposedly artistic exercises. But “cubism” has its reason. To call it nonsense raised to the third power does not explain its origins. This is, of course, not the place to engage in such an explanation. But even here you can indicate the direction in which to look for it. I have an interesting book in front of me: “Du cubisme” by Albert Gleises and Jean Metzinger. Both authors are painters and both belong to the “cubic” school. Let us turn to them, following the rule: audiatur et altera pars. How do they justify their mind-blowing creative techniques? “There is nothing real outside of us,” they say... We do not think to doubt the existence of objects that act on our external senses: but rational certainty is possible only in relation to the image that they evoke in our mind” (Title. ). From here the authors draw the conclusion that we do not know what forms objects themselves have. And on the basis that these forms are unknown to us, they consider themselves to have the right to depict them at their own discretion. They make a reservation worthy of note that they do not want to limit themselves, like the impressionists, to the realm of sensations. “We are looking for the essential,” they assure, “but we are looking for it in our personality, and not in something eternal, laboriously produced by mathematicians and philosophers” (Ibid., p. 31.). In these considerations, as the reader sees, we first of all encounter the idea, already well known to us, that our “I” is the “only reality.” True, here we encounter it in a softened form. Gleizes and Metzinger declare that doubt about the existence of external objects is completely alien to them. But, having admitted the existence of the external world, our authors immediately proclaim it unknowable. And this means that for them there is nothing real except their “I”. If images of objects arise in us as a result of the influence of these latter on our external senses, then it is clear that we cannot talk about the unknowability of the external world: we know it precisely thanks to this influence. Glaze and Metzenzhe are mistaken. Their reasoning about the forms themselves is also very lame. One cannot seriously blame them for their mistakes: such mistakes were made by people infinitely stronger than them in philosophy. But one cannot help but pay attention to this: from the imaginary unknowability of the external world, our authors conclude that we must look for what is essential in “our personality.” This conclusion can be understood in two ways. Firstly, by “personality” we can understand the entire human race; secondly, any given individual person. In the first case we will come to the transcendental idealism of Kant, in the second - to the sophistic recognition of each individual person as the measure of all things. Our authors are inclined precisely to the sophistic interpretation of this conclusion. And once you accept its sophistic interpretation (See especially pp. 43-44.), you can allow yourself absolutely anything in painting, as elsewhere. If instead of “the woman in blue” (“la femme en bleu”: under this title the painting by F. Leger was exhibited at the last autumn “Salon”) I depict several stereometric figures, then who has the right to tell me that I painted an unsuccessful picture? Women are part of the outside world around me. The outside world is unknowable. To portray a woman, I have to appeal to my own “personality,” and my “personality” gives the woman the shape of several randomly scattered cubes, or rather parallelepipeds. These cubes make all visitors to the Salon laugh. But this is not a problem at all. The "crowd" laughs only because it does not understand the artist's language. The artist must under no circumstances yield to it. “An artist who refrains from any concessions, who explains nothing and tells nothing, accumulates an inner strength that illuminates everything around him” (Title of works, p. 42.). And while waiting for the accumulation of this force, all that remains is to draw stereometric figures. Thus, it turns out something like a funny parody of Pushkin’s poem “To the Poet”: Are you satisfied with it, discerning artist? Satisfied? So let the crowd scold him and spit on the altar, where your fire burns, and your tripod shakes in childish playfulness. The comedy of this parody lies in the fact that the “demanding artist” in this case is satisfied with the most obvious nonsense. The appearance of such parodies shows, among other things, that the internal dialectics of social life has now led the theory of art for art's sake to complete absurdity. It is not good for a person to be alone. Today's "innovators" in art are not satisfied with what was created by their predecessors. There is absolutely nothing wrong with this. On the contrary: the desire for something new is very often a source of progress. But not everyone who looks for it finds something truly new. You have to be able to look for something new. Who is blind to the new teachings of social life; for whom there is no other reality other than his “I”, in search of the “new” he will find nothing but new nonsense. It is not good for a person to be alone. It turns out that under current social conditions, art for art's sake does not bear very tasty fruits. The extreme individualism of the era of bourgeois decline closes all sources of true inspiration from artists. It makes them completely blind to what is happening in public life, and condemns them to fruitless fuss with completely meaningless personal experiences and morbidly fantastic fictions. The final result of such fuss is something that not only has no relation whatsoever to any kind of beauty, but also represents an obvious absurdity, which can only be defended with the help of a sophistical distortion of the idealistic theory of knowledge. In Pushkin, the “cold and arrogant people” “meaninglessly” listen to the singing poet. I have already said that under the pen of Pushkin this opposition had its own historical meaning. To understand it, you only need to take into account that the epithets “cold and arrogant” were completely inapplicable to the Russian serf farmer of that time. But for that, they are very well applicable to any representative of that secular “rabble”, which later, with its stupidity, destroyed our great poet. The people who were part of this “rabble” could, without any exaggeration, say about themselves, as the “rabble” says in Pushkin’s poem: We are cowardly, we are treacherous, Shameless, evil, ungrateful, We are cold-hearted eunuchs, Slanderers, slaves, fools, Vices crowd into us like a club. Pushkin saw that it would be ridiculous to give “brave” lessons to this soulless secular crowd; she wouldn't understand anything about them. He was right to proudly turn away from her. Moreover, he was wrong in that, to the great misfortune of Russian literature, he did not turn away from it enough. But now, in advanced capitalist countries, the attitude towards the people of the poet and in general of the artist, who has not been able to shake off the old bourgeois man, is exactly the opposite of what we see in Pushkin: now it is no longer the “people” who can be blamed for stupidity, it is no longer the real people , the leading part of which is becoming more and more conscious, - and artists who “senselessly” listen to the noble calls emanating from the people. These artists, at best, are to blame for the fact that their clocks are 80 years behind. Rejecting the best aspirations of their era, they naively imagine themselves as continuers of the struggle against philistinism that the romantics were engaged in. Both Western Europeans and, following them, our Russian aesthetes, readily expand on the topic of the philistinism of the current proletarian movement. That's funny. Richard Wagner has long shown how unfounded is the reproach of philistinism sent by such gentlemen to the liberation movement of the working class. In Wagner’s very fair opinion, with careful attention to the matter (“Genau betrachtet”), the liberation movement of the working class turns out to be a desire not for philistinism, but from philistinism to a free life, to “artistic humanity” (“zum künstlerischen Menschentum”). It is “the desire for a worthy enjoyment of life, the material means for which a person will no longer have to obtain by spending all his life force.” This acquisition of material means of life by spending all one’s life force now serves as the source of “philistine” feelings. Constant concern for the means of living “has made man weak, servile, stupid and pitiful, turned him into a creature incapable of either loving or hating, into a citizen every minute ready to sacrifice the last remnant of his free will just so that this will be facilitated for him.” care". The liberation movement of the proletariat leads to the elimination of this humiliating and corrupting concern. Wagner found that only its elimination, only the implementation of the liberating aspirations of the proletariat, would make the words of Jesus true: do not worry about what you will eat, etc. (Die Kunst und die Revolution, (R. Wagner, Gesammelte Schriften, II B. Leipzig 1872, S. 40--41).) . He had the right to add that only the implementation of this would deprive of any serious basis the opposition between aesthetics and morality, which we find among supporters of art for art’s sake, for example, in Flaubert (“Les carnets” de Gustave Flaubert (L. Bertrand, Gustave Flaubert, p. 260).). Flaubert found that “virtuous books are boring and deceitful” (“ennuyeux et faux”). He was right. But only because the virtue of the current society, bourgeois virtue, is boring and deceitful. Ancient “virtue” was neither false nor boring in the eyes of the same Flaubert. Meanwhile, its only difference from the bourgeois one is that it was alien to bourgeois individualism. Shirinsky-Shikhmatov, in his capacity as Minister of Public Education under Nicholas I, saw the task of art “in the affirmation of the belief, so important for the life of public and private life, that crime finds a worthy punishment on earth,” that is, in a society carefully cared for Shirinsky-Shikhmatov. It was, of course, a great lie and boring vulgarity. Artists do an excellent job of turning away from such lies and vulgarity. And when we read from Flaubert that in a certain sense “there is nothing more poetic than vice” (Ibid., same page) we understand that the true meaning of this opposition is the opposition of vice to the vulgar, boring and deceitful virtue of the bourgeois moralists Shirinsky-Shikhmatov. But with the elimination of those social orders that give rise to this vulgar, boring and deceitful virtue, the moral need to idealize vice will also be eliminated. I repeat, ancient virtue did not seem vulgar, boring and deceitful to Flaubert, although he, due to the extreme underdevelopment of his socio-political concepts, could, while respecting this virtue, admire such a monstrous denial of it as was the behavior of Nero. In a socialist society, the passion for art for art's sake will become purely logically impossible to the same extent that the vulgarization of public morality, which is now an inevitable consequence of the desire of the ruling class to preserve its privileges, will cease. Flaubert says; “L"art c"est la recherche de l"inutile" (art seeks the useless). In these words it is not difficult to recognize the main idea of ​​Pushkin's poem "Mob". But passion for this thought only means the artist's rebellion against the narrow utilitarianism of a given ruling class or estate. .. With the elimination of classes, this narrow utilitarianism, a close relative of self-interest, will also be eliminated.Self-interest has nothing to do with aesthetics: a judgment of taste always presupposes the absence of considerations of personal benefit on the part of the person expressing it. But personal benefit is another matter, and public benefit is another matter. The desire to be useful to society, which underlay ancient virtue, serves as a source of selflessness, and a selfless act can very easily become - and very often did, as the history of art shows - the subject of aesthetic depiction. It is enough to recall the songs of primitive peoples or, not to go so far, the monument to Harmodius and Aristogeiton in Athens. Even ancient thinkers - for example, Plato and Aristotle - understood perfectly well how the absorption of all his life force by concern for material existence lowers a person. The current ideologists of the bourgeoisie also understand this. They also find it necessary to remove the debilitating burden of constant economic difficulties from a person. But the person they have in mind is a person of the upper social class who lives by exploiting the working people. They see the solution to the problem in the same way that ancient thinkers saw it: in the enslavement of producers by a small group of selected lucky people, more or less approaching the ideal of the “superman”. But if this decision was conservative already in the era of Plato and Aristotle, now it has become ultra-reactionary. And if the conservative Greek slave owners contemporary with Aristotle could count on being able to maintain a dominant position, relying on their own “valor,” then today’s preachers of the enslavement of the masses are very skeptical about the valor of the exploiters from the bourgeois environment. Therefore, they very willingly dream of the appearance at the head of the state of a brilliant superman, who, with the power of his iron will, will strengthen the now shaky edifice of class rule. Decadents, not alien to political interests, are often ardent admirers of Napoleon I. If Renan needed a strong government that would force the “good hillbillies” to work for him while he indulged in reflection, then today’s aesthetes need a social system that would force the proletariat would work while they indulge in sublime pleasures... like drawing and painting cubes and other stereometric figures. Organically incapable of any serious work, they experience sincere indignation at the thought of a social system in which there will be no idleness at all. To live with wolves, howl like a wolf. Fighting... in words with the philistinism, modern bourgeois aesthetes themselves worship the golden calf no worse than the most ordinary philistine. “They think that there is a movement in the field of art,” says Moclair, “in fact there is a movement on the stock exchange of paintings, where they also speculate on unpublished geniuses” (Named works, pp. 319-320.). I will add in passing that this speculation on unpublished geniuses explains, among other things, the feverish pursuit of the “new” that most of today’s artists indulge in. People always strive for the “new” because they are not satisfied with the old. But the question is why it does not satisfy them. Many, many contemporary artists are not satisfied with the old solely because while the public clings to it, their own genius remains “unpublished.” What pushes them to revolt against the old is not love for some new idea, but for the same “single reality” all to the same sweet "me". But such love does not inspire the artist, but only predisposes him to look even at the “Idol of the Belvedere” from the point of view of benefit. “The money question is so closely intertwined with the question of art,” continues Moclair, “that art criticism feels as if in a vice. The best critics cannot express what they think, and the rest express only what they consider appropriate in a given case.” ", because you have to live by your writings. I'm not saying that you should be indignant at this, but it doesn't hurt to be aware of the complexity of the problem" (Title of essays, p. 321). We see: art for art's sake has turned into art for money. And the whole problem that interested Mauclair boils down to determining the reason why this happened. And it is not so difficult to define. “There was a time, such as the Middle Ages, when only surplus, the surplus of production over consumption, was exchanged. “There was another time when not only the surplus, but all products as a whole, all products of industry, passed into the area of ​​commerce, when production became full dependence on exchange... “Finally, the time has come when everything that people are accustomed to looking at as inalienable becomes an object of exchange and bargaining, becomes alienable. At this time, even those things that were previously transferred to others, but are not exchangeable , were given, but not sold, were acquired, but not bought - virtue, love, conviction, knowledge, conscience - everything finally became corrupt. This is the time of general corruption, the time of general corruption, or - to put it in the language of political economy, - the time when every thing, material or moral, has become a selling value, is brought to the market to find its true value there" (K. Marx, "The Poverty of Philosophy", pp. 3-4.). Is it any wonder that in times of general corruption, art also becomes corrupt? Moclair doesn't want to say whether we should be outraged by this. I also have no desire to evaluate this phenomenon from a moral point of view. I strive, as the famous expression goes, not to cry, not to laugh, but to understand. I am not saying that contemporary artists “should” be inspired by the liberating aspirations of the proletariat. No, if an apple tree should give birth to apples, and a pear tree should bear pears, then artists who take the point of view of the bourgeoisie must rebel against these aspirations. Decadent art “should” be decadent. It's unavoidable. And in vain we would become “indignant” about this. But, as the Manifesto of the Communist Party rightly says, “in those periods when the class struggle is nearing its denouement, the process of decomposition among the ruling class, within the entire old society, reaches such a strong degree that some part of the ruling class separates from it and joins the revolutionary "the class carrying the banner of the future. Just as part of the nobility once united with the bourgeoisie, so now part of the bourgeoisie is moving over to the proletariat, namely the bourgeois ideologists who have risen to a theoretical understanding of the entire course of the historical movement." Among the bourgeois ideologists who go over to the side of the proletariat, we see very few artists. This is probably explained by the fact that “only those who think can rise to a theoretical understanding of the entire course of historical movement,” while modern artists—unlike, for example, the great masters of the Renaissance—think extremely little (“Nous touchons ici au défaut de culture générale qui caractérise la plupart des artistes jeunes. Une fréquentation assidue vous démontrera vite qu"ils sont en général très ignorants... incapables ou indifférents devant les antagonismes d"idées et les situations dramatiques actuelles, ils oeuvrent pé niblement à l"écart "de toute l"agitation intellectuelle et sociale, confinés dans les conflits de technique, absorbés par l"apparence matérielle de la peinture plus que par sa signification générale et son influence intellectuelle." Holl, La jeune peinture contemporaine, p. p. 14 --15, Paris 1912.). But be that as it may, we can say with confidence that any significant artistic talent will greatly increase its strength if it is imbued with the great liberating ideas of our time. It is only necessary that these ideas enter his flesh and blood, that he express them precisely as an artist (Here I will gladly refer to Flaubert. He wrote to Georges Sand: “Je crois la forme et le fond... deux entités qui n"existent jamais l"une sans l"autre" ("I I consider form and essence... two essences that never exist one without the other." Correspondance, quatrième série, p. 225). Whoever considers it possible to sacrifice form “for the idea” ceases to be an artist, if he was one before.) "It is also necessary that he be able to appreciate the artistic modernism of the current ideologists of the bourgeoisie on its merits. The ruling class is now in such a position that to go forward means for it to sink down. And this sad fate is shared with it by all its ideologists. The most advanced of them , these are precisely those who have sunk below all their predecessors. When I expressed the views expressed here, Mr. Lunacharsky made me several objections, the most important of which I will consider here. Firstly, he was surprised that I seemed to admit the existence of an absolute criterion beauty. But there is no such criterion. Everything flows, everything changes. By the way, people’s concepts of beauty also change. Therefore, we have no way to prove that contemporary art is actually experiencing a crisis of ugliness. To this I objected and object that, in my opinion, there is no and cannot be an absolute criterion of beauty (“It is not the unconscious whim of fastidious taste that prompts us to desire to find original aesthetic values, not subject to vain fashion, herd imitation. The creative dream of a single imperishable beauty, lifestyle who will “save the world”, enlighten and revive the lost and fallen, feeds on an ineradicable need human spirit penetrate into the creative secrets of the absolute." (V.N. Speransky. "The Social Role of Philosophy", introduction, p. XI, issue I, St. Petersburg, Publishing House "Rosehipnik", marked 1913) People who reason in this way logic obliges us to recognize the absolute criterion of beauty. But people who reason this way are pure-blooded idealists, and I consider myself no less a pure-blooded materialist. Not only do I not recognize the existence of “one incorruptible beauty,” but I don’t even understand what meaning can be associated with with these words: “one incorruptible beauty". Moreover, I am sure that the gentlemen idealists themselves do not understand this. All discussions about such beauty are mere “verbalism”.) People’s concepts of beauty undoubtedly change in the course of the historical process. But if there is no absolute criterion of beauty; if all its criteria are relative, this does not mean that we are deprived of any objective opportunity to judge whether a given artistic design is well executed. Let us assume that the artist wants to paint “a woman in blue.” If then, what he depicts in his picture will, in fact, look like such a woman, so we will say that he managed to paint a good picture. If, instead of a woman dressed in a blue dress, we see on his canvas several stereometric figures, in places more or less densely and more or less roughly painted in blue, then we will say that he painted everything, but not a good one. picture. The more the execution corresponds to the idea or, to use a more general expression, the more the form of the work of art corresponds to its idea, the more successful it is. Here's an objective measure for you. And only because such a standard exists, we have the right to say that the drawings of, for example, Leonardo da Vinci are better than the drawings of some little Themistoclus, who stains paper for his own amusement. When Leonardo da Vinci painted, say, an old man with a beard, he ended up with an old man with a beard. And how it came out! So that when we see him we say: so alive! And when Themistoklus draws such an old man, we would do better if, in order to avoid misunderstandings, we sign: this is an old man with a beard, and not something else. By asserting that there can be no objective measure of beauty, Mr. Lunacharsky committed the very same sin that so many bourgeois ideologists up to and including the Cubists sin: the sin of extreme subjectivism. It is completely incomprehensible to me how a person who calls himself a Marxist can commit such a sin. It must be added, however, that I used the term “beauty” here in a very broad, if you like, too broad sense: to draw an old man with a beard beautifully does not mean to draw a beautiful one, i.e. e. a handsome old man. The field of art is much wider than the field of “beauty”. But throughout its wide field, the criterion I indicated can be applied with equal convenience: the correspondence of the form to the idea. G. Lunacharsky argued (if I understood him correctly) that the form may well correspond to a false idea. But with this I I can't agree. Let's remember de Curel's play "Le repas du lion". At the heart of this play lies, as we know, the false idea that the employer treats his workers in the same way as a lion treats the jackals who feed on the crumbs that fall from his royal table. The question arises: could de Curel have correctly expressed this erroneous idea in his drama? No! This idea is erroneous because it contradicts the actual relationship between the employer and his workers. To depict it in a work of art means to distort reality. And when a work of art distorts reality, then it is unsuccessful. That is why “Le repas du lion” is much lower than de Curel’s talent, and for the same reason the play “At the Royal Gates” is much lower than Hamsun’s talent. Secondly, Mr. Lunacharsky reproached me for being too objectivistic in my presentation. He apparently agreed that the apple tree should bear apples, and the pear tree should bear pears. But he noticed that among the artists who stand on the bourgeois point of view, there are those who are wavering, and that such people must be convinced, and not left to the spontaneous force of bourgeois influences. I confess that I find this reproach even less understandable than the first. In my “abstract” I said and—I would like to think it—showed that contemporary art is falling (I’m afraid that there may be a misunderstanding here too. The word “falling” means to me, corame de raison, a whole process, but not a separate phenomenon. This process has not yet ended, just as the social process of the fall of the bourgeois order has not ended. It would be strange, therefore, to think that today's bourgeois ideologists are completely incapable of producing any outstanding works. Such works are possible, of course, even now. But the chances of their appearance fatally are decreasing. In addition, even outstanding works now bear the stamp of an era of decline. Let's take the above-mentioned Russian trinity: if Mr. Filosofov is devoid of any talent in any field, then Mrs. Gippius has some artistic talent, and Mr. Merezhkovsky is even a very talented artist. But it is easy to see that, for example, his last novel (Alexander I) was irreparably damaged by his religious mania, which in turn is a phenomenon characteristic of an era of decline. In such eras, even very great talents are far from giving all that they could give. Under more favorable social conditions.). As the reason for this phenomenon, to which no person who sincerely loves art can remain indifferent, I pointed to the fact that the majority of today's artists adhere to the bourgeois point of view and remain completely inaccessible to the great liberating ideas of our time. The question is, how can this instruction influence the hesitant? If it is convincing, then it should encourage those who are wavering to switch to the point of view of the proletariat. And this is all that can be asked from an essay devoted to the consideration of the issue of art, and not to the presentation and defense of the principles of socialism. Last not least. G. Lunacharsky, considering it impossible to prove the fall of bourgeois art, finds that I would act more rationally if I contrasted bourgeois ideals with a harmonious system - as I remember, he put it - of concepts opposite to them. And he told the audience that such a system would be developed over time. And such an objection completely surpasses my understanding. If this system is still being developed, then it is clear that it does not exist yet. And if it doesn’t exist, then how could I oppose it to bourgeois views? What kind of harmonious system of concepts is this? Modern scientific socialism undoubtedly represents a completely coherent theory. And it has the advantage of already existing. But, as I already said, it would be very strange if, having taken up reading an “abstract” on the topic “art and social life,” I began to expound the doctrine of modern scientific socialism, for example, the theory of surplus value. The only good thing is what appears on time and in its place. It is possible, however, that under a harmonious system of concepts Mr. Lunacharsky meant those considerations about proletarian culture that his closest like-minded person, Mr. Bogdanov, recently put forward in print. In this case, his last objection boiled down to the fact that I would have become even more alert if Mr. Bogdanov learned a little. Thanks for the advice. But I don't intend to use it. And for anyone who, due to inexperience, would be interested in Mr. Bogdanov’s brochure “On Proletarian Culture,” I will remind you that this brochure was quite successfully ridiculed in “Modern World” by another of Mr. Lunacharsky’s closest like-minded people, Mr. Aleksinsky.


Art: Collection of articles / G. V. Plekhanov; With introductory articles: 1) L. Axelrod-Orthodox “On the attitude of G. V. Plekhanov to art according to personal memories”; 2) V. Fritsche “G. V. Plekhanov and scientific aesthetics.” - Moscow: “New Moscow”, 1922. - 216 p.

[Preface]

Marxist literature on art is known to be extremely poor.

Of the greatest theoreticians of Marxism, only G. V. Plekhanov definitely set the task of constructing a Marxist doctrine of art.

G. V. Plekhanov approached the solution of the problem he posed with his characteristic breadth of view and interest, subjecting to the study not only literature, moreover, on a global scale, but also the plastic arts and music - (it must be remembered that not all , what he thought and said about this subject is published) - covering the creativity of both primitive tribes and highly civilized peoples, and it seems that there is not a single fundamentally important question in this area that would not have been put forward by him: the origin and essence art, the influence of the environment on it, the meaning of a “brilliant” personality, factors in the evolution of artistic creativity, form and content, etc., etc. - all these questions were posed and resolved by him in the spirit of historical materialism, in the spirit of the theory of class struggle , for only “by taking into account the class struggle and studying its manifold vicissitudes, can we at least satisfactorily explain the spiritual history of civilized societies,” and therefore, anyone “who is not aware of the struggle, the centuries-old and varied process of which constitutes history, he cannot be a conscious art critic.” ¹)

True, G.V. Plekhanov did not systematically set out his “scientific aesthetics” anywhere, because he did not initially set such a task for himself, and in any case he did not have the time to complete it. However, both in the articles printed below and in his other piles (“Basic questions of Marxism”, On the question of the monistic view of history”, “On the role of the individual in history”, “The aesthetic theory of Chernyshevsky”), as well as in his articles , devoted to issues of literature and literary criticism ("Belinsky's Literary Views", "The Fates of Russian Criticism", in articles about populist writers, etc.), such a great variety of theoretical positions and specific illustrations are scattered that on the basis of them it would not be at all difficult to recreate in a systematic form the basic principles of “scientific aesthetics”, the doctrine of art on the foundations of Marxist sociology.

____________

¹) The fate of Russian criticism.

²) Before his death, he regretted that he did not have time to write a book about art.

It should not be forgotten that Plekhanov posed these questions not as an armchair scientist, not as a “specialist,” but always in combat, as a militant Marxist, and therefore his articles on these issues are usually of a polemical nature, taking up arms against those who are not sufficiently correct or clearly false methods of research, for example, against the exclusively biological point of view as applied to primitive art, or against the essentially idealistic sociology of Taine, or against the “philosophical” criticism of Volynsky, or against the populist approach of Ivanov-Razumnik, etc., and even the most The issues he wrote about were usually of such a combative, polemical nature, combining scientific significance with topical relevance.

This militant position, depriving him of the opportunity to systematize his views, at the same time allowed him to discover, along with enormous erudition and methodological clarity, the brilliant gift of a polemicist-fighter, a destroyer of bourgeois methods and values, and what, if not this, is the significance of the ideologist of the fighting proletariat?

Every young Marxist should become familiar with the following published articles by the founder of “scientific aesthetics.” The first “On Art” (reprinted from the collection “For Twenty Years”) clarifies the fundamental positions of historical materialism in its application to art. The following (actually two articles from the collection “Criticism of Our Critics”: “Art among Primitive Peoples” and “More about Art among Primitive Peoples”) explores the main problems of primitive art, indirectly illuminating the question of the origin and original meaning of art. Article "French" dramatic literature and French painting of the 18th century. from a sociological point of view” (“For Twenty Years”) shows, using a particular example in a masterful analysis, how class evolution and class psychology predetermine the evolution of artistic “form” and artistic “content” in the field of literature, theater and painting. Finally, the last article, given initially as a lecture in Paris and Liege (reprinted from the Sovremennik magazine, 1912, No. 11 and 12 and 1913, No. 1), brilliantly reveals, on the one hand, the various social combinations that lead in other cases to the dominance of the theory of “art for art’s sake”, and in others - to the triumph of the theory of “art for life”, and on the other hand, raises the question of the artistic and social value of modern art, making it clear that the art of a class leaving the historical stage, must inevitably lead to extreme subjectivism, symbolism, mysticism, lack of ideas and technicalism, and that the incorrectness and wretchedness of thought caused by the class affiliation of the creators of such art fatally reduces the very artistic value of their creations.

Reviewing G. V. Plekhanov’s articles on art, you involuntarily regret that it does not exist, because at the present time, when obvious chaos reigns in the field of artistic creativity and aesthetic assessments and a strong public opinion on these issues has not yet crystallized in party and Soviet circles, his instructions would, of course, be of enormous value, and who would consider it possible not to listen to his voice in this area?

ABOUT G. V. PLEKHANOV’S ATTITUDE TO ART, ACCORDING TO PERSONAL MEMORIES ¹).

¹) Speech delivered at a meeting convened by the sociological department of the Academy of Artistic Sciences and dedicated to honoring the memory of G. V. Plekhanov on the occasion of the 4th anniversary of his death and published in No. 5 of the magazine “Under the Banner of Marxism”.

Comrades! I am speaking today from the sociological department of the Academy of Artistic Sciences and will stick strictly to my topic. I will not touch on Plekhanov as a political fighter, and in general his multifaceted personality, rich in diverse spiritual content, but will briefly characterize his attitude to art based on my personal memories. But let me nevertheless make a few preliminary remarks. The historian of materialism F. A. Lange, defining materialism as a worldview that forms the basis of positive knowledge, reproached it for poverty with subjective ideological content.

Ideological metaphysics, although it is the poetry of concepts, can be proud of its kinship with religion, poetry and art, and this is a great advantage.

In a sense, F. A. Lange was right. Materialism before Marx and Engels, indeed, kept aloof from the historical content of human culture. His main field of study was the fundamentals of natural science. Only in critical eras did materialists turn their attention to the state and ethics, such as T. Hobbes and the French materialists of the 18th century. Aesthetics and art should have seemed to them to be an exclusively subjective area, to which it is impossible to apply scientific methods of research, and what cannot be the subject of positive science is not of interest to materialists. Only Diderot, partly following his deeply artistic nature and the pressing demands of the era, laid some foundation for scientific aesthetics.

The materialist understanding of history, which set as its goal to give a strictly scientific explanation of all historical content, should, naturally, pay attention to art.

But the founders of the materialist understanding of history, Marx and Engels, were not only armchair thinkers, but also fighters on the battlefield of life. Theoretical tasks directly related to the interests of the practical movement of the proletariat were in the foreground. Issues of art were therefore relegated to the background.

In the found draft of the preface to Marx's Critique of Political Economy, there are three pages devoted to art. But, unfortunately, the manuscript ends. As always with Marx, the content of these pages is interesting due to its deep approach to the problem, but this is incidental. It is important that Marx, in the preface, where the formulation of the materialist understanding of history is given, dwells specifically on the question of art; Engels left us nothing in this area.

G. V. Plekhanov paid serious attention to the problems of art. G.V.’s attraction to this problem is explained, in my opinion, by the following reasons. Firstly, G. V. Plekhanov was an extremely complex, artistic person: beauty and art played an outstanding role in his spiritual life. Secondly, G.V. received his revolutionary, spiritual education from the works of Belinsky, Chernyshevsky and Dobrolyubov. In all European countries, literary criticism was of enormous importance in critical eras. But here in Russia she has played a particularly outstanding role. Under the conditions of police autocracy, artistic criticism was a protesting, revolutionary principle, subjecting literature, and in its face, Russian reality, to critical examination. Art criticism had historical significance. Our famous critics combined a philosophical worldview and deep artistic appreciation with revolutionary thought. G. V followed in the footsteps of his first teachers - Belinsky, Chernyshevsky. As you know, G.V. dedicated an extensive article to Belinsky; Chernyshevsky and his work became the topic of an extensive work.

Plekhanov felt such a deep affection and such a strong spiritual kinship for “The Furious Vissarion” that his dying wish was to be buried near the grave of the brilliant critic. This wish has been fulfilled. The ashes of G.V. rest next to the remains of the brilliant critic.

From what has been said, I think it is quite obvious what strong influence Russian social thought had an impact on the spiritual development of the founder of Russian Marxism. Further, G.V.’s attitude to art was determined by another moment that had decisive and final significance.

This point is the teachings of Marx and Engels, the views of the founders of scientific socialism on social development and their idea of ​​the nature and content of the revolution.

The populists of the 70s, to whose movement Plekhanov belonged in his youth, were more than indifferent to art. Going among the people required simplification. For them, art was tolerable because it was tendentious, i.e. since the “artistic” work sinned against the requirements of aesthetics. Reshetnikov’s tendentious stories, devoid of artistic merit, were placed above “Childhood, Adolescence and Youth,” which found proper appreciation only in select literary circles. This attitude towards art flowed from the entire worldview of populism. Another thing is the revolutionary teaching arising from historical materialism. There can be no talk here of simplification, of adapting to the masses by lowering cultural forms. The task of representatives of scientific socialism, as is known, is mainly to develop the consciousness of the masses, not only political consciousness, as many are inclined to think, but comprehensive: scientific, ethical and aesthetic. The form of propaganda of socialist ideas must correspond to in-depth, serious scientific content. The true preaching of a Marxist should lift up the listener or reader, and therefore crude form, demagoguery, and cheap effects are as inappropriate as such forms of expression of thought in a scientific work. The popularity of the presentation, necessary for propaganda to the masses, requires an even more urgent artistic form.

Plekhanov was imbued with these views.

In support of what has been said, allow me to cite the following, in my opinion, unusually characteristic episode.

In 1905, after the significant January 9th, Gapon arrived in Geneva, who immediately after his arrival came to Plekhanov. I will not tell the interesting, however, details of his appearance, subsequent negotiations, conversations and meetings with this unfortunate man. In connection with my topic today, only the following scene deserves attention.

Gapon wrote something like a poem, the theme of which was the march of the Petrograd proletariat, with him at its head, to the royal palace. The poem was written in rude, demagogic tones, the vulgar content was expressed in a correspondingly rude, demagogic form. Gapon decided to read it to Plekhanov and me. I read it in G.V. Gapon’s office. There was no one there except the three of us. During the reading, G.V. listened, as always, seriously, attentively, without missing, I am sure, a single word - G.V.’s manner of listening was well known to me. It would be impossible to determine from the expression of his face whether he liked the thing or not, which, by the way, did not stem from deliberate secrecy, but was a consequence of complete attention to what he was reading. Gapon read, only occasionally glancing at his listeners, especially, of course, at G.V. The reading ended, there was a moment of silence. Then Plekhanov stood up. I saw Plekhanov over long periods and in different situations. But this was the first and only time I saw him. G.V., generally having a rather impressive appearance, seemed to immediately grow many times over and somehow suddenly became extremely large and majestic: “So you think,” he turned to Gapon, “that people can and should be treated with such childish fairy tales? The people are the greatest force in the historical movement, the people are a great thing, and turning to them with soothing tales is a direct and unjustifiable crime. To go among the people means to be able to speak seriously, and, accordingly, to clothe your speech in a simple, clear and truly beautiful form, but you have imagined that the people are made up of boys, and that therefore you can tell them vulgar fairy tales.”

Gapon was very embarrassed and turned terribly pale. Then Plekhanov looked, letting me understand that it was better for me to leave, since my presence prevented him from developing his political speech properly: he still spared Gapon. I left. The next day Gapon came to me. I turned to him with a question: “What, Father Gapon, how did you like Plekhanov yesterday?” - Let me make a digression and tell my impression of Gapon. It is as follows: the unfortunate aspects of this man’s character led him to the most terrible crime - betrayal. Nevertheless, Gapon was a very sensitive person, and in his soul there was an undoubted contact with the masses. Therefore, he vividly felt a great man and a true representative of the people and answered my question in this way: “You know, Lyubov Isakovna, if my habits as a priest had not offended Plekhanov, I would have fallen on my knees before him and kissed his feet; he is a true representative of the people."

He understood Plekhanov. I am convinced that this trait of Georgy Valentinovich - his understanding and interpretation of the development of the consciousness of the masses - determined his deep attitude towards art. He dealt with issues of art very seriously.

Starting with the suit, which was always decent, despite poverty - I recognized Plekhanov and his family in that era when need was the absolute ruler of the house, when he had only one suit - G.V. never had a downcast appearance and never looked like the usual type, the type of Russian nihilist emigrant. From his costume to his style, which he worked on with extreme care, he was an esthete in the true, highest, true sense of the word. And as already mentioned above, this aestheticism was in full connection with his ideas about the cultural meaning of the proletarian movement.

Without having the slightest desire to talk with you on theoretical topics, I will, with your permission, continue my speech with cursory memories of G. V. Plekhanov’s attitude to art.

Four years ago, just this evening, the amazing news of the death of G.V. came to me. Vividly remembering this difficult hour, I would like to dwell on the personal, intimate side of Plekhanov’s relationship with art. I hope and am confident that you, who have come here to honor the memory of the founder of Russian Marxism, share this sentiment with me.

Plekhanov always read fiction. I lived in his house for two years, from 1892 to 1894, and subsequently lived nearby for two years, in the next house. (The Plekhanovs lived in Geneva, Rue de Candelle 6, and I lived on the same street, no. 4). Consequently, I had every opportunity to observe the process of G.V.’s work. I always read G.V. And G.V., in my mind, exists only with a book. And among the reading on a variety of issues, fiction occupied a prominent place. Of the Russian artists, Pushkin, Gogol, Tolstoy and Ouspensky were favorites. He treated Dostoevsky with obvious dislike.

I remember how once, in a conversation about Russian literature, I expressed the idea that Dostoevsky is a more democratic writer than Tolstoy and Turgenev, who have a strong sense of belonging to the nobility. Dostoevsky, I said, is sensitive to the oppressed. “Yes,” answered G.V., “Dostoevsky, indeed, sympathizes with the oppressed, but this oppressed person must be at least a little crazy.” He also loved to read Nekrasov, but the form did not satisfy him in everything. However, attitude. G.V. to Nekrasov was expressed in his article about the poet.

Of the literature of the later generation, G.V. loved and rated Chekhov and Korolenko very highly. I read and re-read Chekhov often. In Gorky, of course, he recognized great talent, but he was offended by the coarseness of the form, the low degree of aesthetic culture, and the romance of tramps in Gorky’s work did not correspond to the general direction of Plekhanov. In German literature he was a deep admirer of Goethe. He did not like Schiller, and this dislike for Schiller’s work is explained, in my opinion, by one main feature of G.V. Plekhanov. Plekhanov was distinguished by his extraordinary sincerity, in the real meaning of the word, that very sincerity that Romain Rolland says is such a rare quality as intelligence, beauty and kindness. Plekhanov was offended by the slightest falsehood, the most insignificant artificiality. Whatever he did, whatever he talked about, he was all there; this is sincerity. Schiller’s work seemed to him somewhat elevated, however, there were exceptions - G.V. was very fond of “William Tell.” He worshiped the genius of Goethe, in the literal sense of the word, he especially admired the first part of Faust, he considered the second part not artistic. He took special interest in Mephistopheles. The thinking of this philosopher of dialectic and destruction was in some way consistent with the dialectical method. It is not for nothing that Hegel and Engels quoted him so often. But while placing a high value on “Faust,” G.V. found one element unnecessary, violating the greatness of this creation.

Gretchen's tragedy of love was such an unnecessary element. This tragedy spoiled, in his opinion, the overall picture. Faust, this is the tragedy of knowledge, this is the epic of man and humanity. And the tragedy of Gretchen’s love is a small, insignificant episode, Mephistopheles, this philosopher-destroyer, Satan-fighter of God, and what does he do in the tragedy of “Faust” - helping Faust seduce 14 year old girl. At the same time, he lovingly referred to the passage in Hegel where the great German idealist speaks with stern irony about the ingrained habit of artists always tinkering with the plot, just as young Hans fell in love with young Gretchen. Plekhanov fully supported Hegel’s point of view that it was time to finally stop considering sexual romantic love as the main theme in creativity. Romantic love, of course, has its own significance, G.V. did not deny this, of course, but its significance is nothing in comparison with other phenomena of historical activity.

G.V. loved Heine very much, mainly his satire. From intimate lyrics, G.V. loved “Stormy Stream” and “Azra”. He always listened to this romance by Rubinstein with admiration and often asked his wife Rosalia Markovna to sing it (his wife had a wonderful voice).

Of English literature, his favorite authors were Shakespeare, Byron and Shelley, and he had a particularly touching feeling for Dickens. In Shakespeare's works, he highly valued historical dramas, which reflected the political life of England and some features of the Renaissance. He loved Hamlet, whom he sometimes quoted, noting: “That’s what the Danish prince thought.” He often quoted Macbeth. But he couldn’t stand “King Lear” and considered this dramatic figure an eccentric old man. Not being in agreement with this assessment, I expressed my view on this tragedy of Shakespeare, and one day it seemed to me that G.V. had given up. This was under the following circumstances; at the end of the nineties, when there was a struggle between the “Emancipation of Labor” Group and the revolutionary Social Democrats and economists adjacent to it. The “Emancipation of Labor” group, after many unpleasant vicissitudes, gave the union its revolutionary property: a font and some other printing supplies: The “Emancipation of Labor” group was left without tools. It was necessary to print something, and now Plekhanov found himself in a dramatic situation. At that moment, turning to him, I remarked: But you see, G.V., you are now in the position of “King Lear.” He smiled, after thinking a little, he replied, “But King Lear is still an eccentric old man.” This attitude towards King Lear did not stem from the whim of individual taste, it, I think, was rooted in his revolutionary nature. Despite all the versatility of G.V., he, apparently, was not able to penetrate the tragedy of the king, who was prematurely deprived of his throne.

Being actually engaged in art and the development of artistic movements in Russian literature, G.V. always rushed around with the idea of ​​​​subjecting research to this great branch of human culture from a materialistic point of view. He began this work with complete certainty in the early nineties. And so, while working on this topic, he read an incredible number of books. I have a significant number of Plekhanov’s letters; from these letters you can see how much he read. The fact is that he lacked his own extensive library, or the Geneva libraries, and I sent him books from Bern. The Berne State Library had the opportunity to order books from German libraries for certain people. I remember well how I pestered the librarian, and I immediately cannot help but express admiration for this wonderful old man, who always met my requests. Books on aesthetics were sent in large packages to Plekhanov in Geneva. These were works of classics in aesthetics. But abstract metaphysical aesthetics, which poses the problem of beauty in itself, could give little to the theorist of historical materialism.

The question was posed on a purely historical basis, namely: what is the origin of art? G.V. turned to ethnology, which he knew very thoroughly up to that time. But the problems of art required consideration of facts of a different order in culture. And so the work began. I again began to bother the librarian of the state library. But the dear Swiss retained his old attitude.

I can say with complete conviction that Plekhanov read everything that was available on this issue when he finally read his article on primitive art (it was published in the collection “Criticism of Our Critics”). He came to give it as a lecture in Bern. In general, it should be noted that G.V. loved to read his works before they were published to the public. The immediate impression that the composition made on the listeners was of great importance to him. This is explained by the fact that Plekhanov was a fighter and that the main desire of his work was the propaganda of his favorite Marxist ideas. The public remained generally indifferent to the lectures on primitive art. She did not understand Plekhanov at all. It seemed to her that we were talking about primitive culture in its general sense, which she had read about in famous books Lippert et al.

I remember Plekhanov’s story about how a girl came up to him after a lecture and said with a decisive look: “But I knew all this,” to which G.V. replied: “I sincerely envy you, I only learned some things 2-3 times.” weeks ago." This encyclopedist undoubtedly reflected the general attitude of the majority of listeners¹).

____________

¹) This was in 1903 (before the second congress, in the summer); The Iskra team decided to organize a series of lectures in the Berne Colony, where there were a lot of youth sympathetic to Social Democracy, Plekhanov gave 8 lectures on art, Lenin - 7 lectures on the agrarian question, and I - 6 lectures on Kant’s philosophy.

Plekhanov continued his work stubbornly and seriously, but the complexity of the subject, on the one hand, and the high demands, on the other, work on “The Development of Russian Social Thought,” on the third, fatally pushed the planned essay on art into the background.

About three months before his death, when G.V., apparently, was summing up the general results of his life and work, he noted with deep regret that he somehow failed to use all the accumulated material on issues of art and complete the planned work. He attached colossal cultural and utilitarian propaganda significance to art.

In a general cultural sense, art was supposed, from Plekhanov’s point of view, to replace religion. Religion, being a fruit of fantasy and imagination, pretends to be reality, while art, reflecting reality, is what it really is - a fruit of artistic imagination. In particular, the theater should replace the church. A number of authors and artists who were highly valued by Plekhanov passed before us. Among them we saw both realists and romantics. The question arises, what direction in art did Plekhanov adhere to? It goes without saying that talent is in the foreground in artistic creativity, which explains the fact that Byron and Shelley were among the favorite poets. But as far as the general direction is concerned, Plekhanov stood on the solid ground of realism. Art has as its task to reflect reality, but not only as it is, but as it should be; in other words, reality in its forward movement and development. It is clear, therefore, that the ought, the ideals that should be reflected in artistic creativity, are also contained in reality. This point of view can be briefly formulated in the words of Goethe:

„Greift nur hinein ins volle Menschenleben,

Ein jeder lebt"s, nicht vielen ist"s bekannt,

Und wo ihr"s packt, da ist"es interessant.“

G.V. had an extremely negative attitude towards symbolic art. Admiring Ibsen's colossal talent and recognizing his enormous dramatic power, he still could not talk about Peer-Gynt without irritation. It should also be added that the realistic direction in art flowed from the general principle of the materialist understanding of history. It was a logical consequence of that high assessment of the historical process itself and the general optimistic view of human history.

What else can I say to you in conclusion? It’s a mournful hour, and it’s hard, too hard to remember that four years ago, in the prime of his spiritual powers, a great and noble thinker, the founder of Russian Marxism and one of the pillars of the international proletarian movement, died prematurely. G.V.'s life was a beautiful, artistic poem, full of deep dramatic episodes. More than once G.V. was in the position of Ibsen's doctor Shtokman. But such is the lot of truly historical figures.

17 notes were submitted from the public with various questions. Here are the answers to some questions that were given by L. I. Axelrod.

How did Plekhanov feel about Tolstoy? Let me point out that there is an article by Plekhanov about Tolstoy, published in 1910 in the Moscow Bolshevik magazine Mysl. According to my personal recollections, the general assessment is this: as an artist, Tolstoy is strong and great, but as a thinker, he is weak.

Plekhanov was a revolutionary from the ground up, and the principle of non-resistance to evil through violence, of course, could not evoke any sympathy in him from any point of view.

Who was Plekhanov's favorite composer? G.V. loved music in general, but Beethoven made the deepest and strongest impression on him. The powerful harmony, strength and heroism in Beethoven’s work found a full response in Plekhanov’s complex and strong soul. I remember one, as it seems to me, curious episode of the following nature. I had to listen to Beethoven’s performance several times together with G.V., and I always heard enthusiastic reviews from him about the work of the great master. One day, a wonderful choir in Geneva (it was, and perhaps still exists, a city choir, consisting of 500 people, all the musical forces of the city took part in it, no matter what class) decided to stage Beethoven’s solemn mass.

Famous soloists and a wonderful orchestra were invited, in short, much was expected from the concert. I expressed my desire to go to the concert, asking immediately if he and his family were going to the concert. G.V. replied that he does not like religious music. It should be noted that G.V. had complete aversion to religion. He could not understand how educated and intelligent people could find subjective satisfaction in the worldview of their grandmothers and great-grandmothers. That, of course, did not in the least prevent him from considering the scientific, historical study of religion a serious task. But this is by the way. I'm going back to the concert. I continued to insist that the concert would undoubtedly be very interesting. Rosalia Markovna Plekhanova joined, and it ended with G.V., his whole family and I going to listen to the “solemn mass.” The performance was classic, deeply soulful, and now I remember with amazing clarity this reverent grandeur and power of feeling. G.V. listened seriously, intently, and the further he went, the more clearly that strong effect, which the performance of the “solemn mass” had on him.

5. Proletarian movement and bourgeois art... 193

Sample pages